PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen The following full text is a publisher's version. For additional information about this publication click this link. http://hdl.handle.net/2066/91334 Please be advised that this information was generated on 2015-01-24 and may be subject to change. Gapping Studies in Generative Grammar The goal of Studies in Generative Grammar is to publish those texts that are representative of recent advances in the theory of formal grammar. Too many studies do not reach the public they deserve because of the depth and detail that make them unsuitable for publications in article form. We hope that the present series will make these studies available to a wider audience than has been hitherto possible. Jan Koster Henk van Riemsdijk AnnekeNeijt A contribution to Sentence Grammar ¥ FORIS P U B LIC ATIO NS / D O R D R EC H T H O L LA N D / C IN N A M IN S O N / USA Second revised edition 1980 This study has been supported fin a n cia lly by the Netherlands Organization fo r the Advancement o f Pure Research (grant 30-42), © 1979 by Foris Publications - Dordrecht. No p a rt o f this book m ay be translated o r reproduced in any fo rm , by p rin t, p h o to p rin t, o r any o th e r means, w ith o u t w ritte n permission from th e author. ISBN 90 70176 12 2 Printed in the Netherlands by Intercontinental Graphics. to my parents Acknowledgements W i t h g r e a t p l e a s u r e I ta k e the o p p o r t u n i t y to e x p r e s s m y gratitude feeling Groot to of those obligation Institute, frie n d s , who supported X mention all, who contributed one thi s the partly way or enterprise. staff as of the colleagues, the other. v o l v e d w a s A r n o l d E vers, m y s u p e r v i s o r , With Most a A.W. de partly as deeply in the o ne w h o s e f a s c i n a t i n g v i e w s on l i n g u i s t i c s a r o u s e d m y .interest in the field. It w a s he w h o f i r s t set m e on i n v e s t i g a t i n g the G a p p i n g p h e no m e n a , and stimulated proceedings had syncratic approach, scientious mored directions. me the to start this project. While the the ins a n d o u t s of h i s i d i o final participation, Schultink, made me to p u t up w i t h result and his Indispensable o w e s a lot very were liberal the to h i s c o n and g o o d - h u comments of Henk the p r o m o t e r of t h i s thes i s , w h o s e c a r e f u l r e a d i n g aware of m a n y d e f e c t s , and the d i s c u s s i o n s , varying in i n t e n s i t y a n d s u b j e c t , b u t all m o s t f r u i t f u l , w i t h M a r i a n ne Elsakkers, Ger Steven Krauwer, len en W i m the many de Kees Haan, he Huybregts, Geert Koefoed, Ste v e n s , Louis des T o m b e , Mieke Tro m m e To W i m in p a r t i c u l a r I am i n d e b t e d f o r Zonneveld. hours Riny spent helping me reach the finish and produce a readable version. M a n y t h a n k s I owe to l i n g u i s t s o u t s i d e the A.W. de G r o o t Institute: David committee, Jan Koster, improved an comments on N e i j t hurst were Lightfoot, earlier English examples. version. (1978b). so k i n d as third and Frans member Zwarts. Hans den of my dissertation T h e i r comment's m u c h Besten gave useful Bi l l D o t s o n S m i t h a n d J a m e s P a n k to gi v e t h e i r n a t i v e j u d g e m e n t s on the •? viii The members of the research group m e t a b o l i s m of the U n i v e r s i t y H o s p i t a l cially Sijmen Duursma, Wilma Weerens, were Janthony so k i n d as f o r c a l c i u m a n d bone at R.U. U t r e c h t , e s p e Haymakers, J a n R o e l o f s , a nd to o f f e r me t h e i r h o s p i t a l i t y a n d s h a r e w i t h m e the m e r i t s of m o d e r n t y p e w r i t i n g . Special Piet. Their thanks faith and love go to my and dear support made parents this and Jan and study possible in the f i r s t place. Anneke Neijt Utrecht Introduction Traditionally, are a major reductions point of in departure coordinate for the g r a m m a r a n d the n a t u r e of g r a m m a t i c a l rules. mational used analysis of language, from the mational variables 1957, outset rules an d 35). Due theoretical restructuring to constraints, notion of coordinate towards of existence of t r a nsfor f o r the n e c e s s i t y of (cf. C h o m s k y coordinations, for mirror the first image further time, r ules, such as t r a n s d e ri - a c r o s s - t h e - b o a r d a p p l i c a t i o n o f rules, recoverability a p p e a r e d for the s a m e r e a son. in sentence In the t r a n s f o r as f o r s t r i n g s study appeared operations, and the to a r g u e as w e l l the vational the to m o t i v a t e proposals of reduction p henomena have been especially for c a t e g o r i e s constructions study of deletion. Others dis The p r e s e n t s t u d y o f r e d u c t i o n s constructions maintains the t h e o r y of g r a m m a r . this orientation It b r i n g s the c h a r a c t e r i s t i c s o f the c o n j u n c t i o n r e d u c t i o n rul e of G a p p i n g to b e a r u p o n the general principles t hat constrain the notion of transfor m a t ion. The tion starting-point between initial of the f i r s t chapter and non-initial is the d i s t i n c coordination, which is u s e d to i l l u s t r a t e a r e m a r k a b l e s t r u c t u r a l d i f f e r e n c e b e t w e e n English an d D u t c h . As Dutch are their reduction centrates cl u s i o n s . Backward fr o m shown on to regards bear nonphrasal First, in the main striking The of i ssue, the Reduction, English resemblance remainder conjunction, reduction Conjunction reduction a phenomena. the of in first conjunct, turns other conjuncts, out vis-à-vis chapter resulting to be and 1 con two con so-called different c a p t u r e d by G a p p i n g . X The latter former made in tion, is clearly almost belongs certainly recent to s e n t e n c e g r a m m a r , doe s analyses not. between Lef t P e r i p h e r a l D e l e t i o n , abandoned. The sum of Second, Forward the whereas the distinction Conjunction Reduc Conjunct Movement and Gapping these phenomena can be shown to discussions of r e s u l t f r o m a g e n e r a l i z e d rule of G a p p i n g . The second Gapping. The chapter’ ’s u r v e y s notion some of recoverability recent is u s e d to a r g u e that t here is n o n e e d f o r t his r ule to r e f e r to s p e c i f i c c o n s t i t u ents . The t h i r d c h a p t e r shows, standing allo w s , that the as c a r e f u l l y as c u r r e n t u n d e r variable between the G a p p i n g is s e n s i t i v e to the I s l a n d C o n s t r a i n t s . re is no a priori constraints trivial on reason to e x p e c t movements, WH-movement. restrictions This from implies general that G a pping it t u r n s o u t t h a t parallelism between the s c o p e tha t an y remnants should obey there is a n o n of G a p p i n g a n d t h a t of attempt principles of Although the such to derive as s h o u l d a p p l y b o t h to m o v e m e n t r u l e s a n d to G a p p i n g . these Subjacency A revised n o t i o n of S u b j a c e n c y is p r o p o s e d to o b t a i n this r esult. Table of Contents ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS VII INTRODUCTION IX C H A P T E R 1: TH E S Y N T A X O F C O O R D I N A T I O N 1. P h r a s a l c o n j u n c t i o n : 1 i n i t i a l vs. n o n - i n i t i a l coordination • 1 1.1. V P s t r u c t u r e s a n d u n d e r l y i n g S O V 7 1.2. S s t r u c t u r e s 13 2. C o o r d i n a t i o n o f n o n c o n s t i t u e n t s 2.1. G a p p i n g 16 . 18 2.1.1. M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n c y 19 2.1.2. V a r i a b l e s as t a r g e t s f o r d e l e t i o n or interpretation 19 2.1.3. M u l t i p l e t a r g e t d e l e t i o n 22 2.1.4. Island sensitivity 23 2.1.5. The d o m a i n s o f G a p p i n g 24 2.1.6. 2.1.7. The C o o r d i n a t e S t r u c t u r e C o n s t r a i n t and across-the-board applications 30 Conclusion: 37 the f o r m u l a t i o n o f G a p p i n g 2.2. B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n 39 2.2.1. M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n c y 40 2.2.2. The t a r g e t of B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n Reduction 41 2.2.3. One t a r g e t d e l e t i o n 42 2.2.4. Island sensitivity 43 2.2.5. The d o m a i n s o f B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n Reduction ' 45 xii 3. L i m i t a t i o n s in d e s c r i p t i v e d e v i c e s 47 3.1. P h r a s a l c o n j u n c t i o n vs. r e s t r u c t u r i n g / relabeling 47 3.2. F o r w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n 3.3. 50 Left Peripheral Deletion 57 3.4. C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t 62 F o o t n o t e s to c h a p t e r 1 66 C H A P T E R 2: T HE R U L E OF G A P P I N G 73 1. E a r l i e r r u l e s o f G a p p i n g 73 1.1. H a n k a m e r ' s U n a c c e p t a b i l i t y 73 1.2. S t i l l i n g s 1975 1.3. L a n g e n d o e n 1975 76 . 1.4. K u n o 1976 81 82 2. D e s c r i p t i v e a d e q u a c y 2.1. The d o m a i n o f the rule 85 87 2.2. The r e m n a n t s 89 2.3. The g a p s 93 2.4. C o n s e q u e n c e s for the f o r m u l a t i o n o f G a p p i n g 95 3. R e c o v e r a b i l i t y 97 F o o t n o t e s to c h a p t e r 2 107 C H A P T E R 3: C O N S T R A I N T S 109 1, C o n s t r a i n i n g the r e m n a n t s 110 1.1, M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n c y 110 1.2, F i e n g o ' s H e a d C o n d i t i o n r e f o r m u l a t e d a s a Maximization Principle 113 1.3, V a r i a t i o n s o n A - o v e r - A 116 1.4, S a g v e r s u s H a n k a m e r 122 1.5, C o n c l u s i o n 128 2. C o n s t r a i n t s on the g a p s 2.1. O b s e r v a t i o n s 129 129 2.1.1. Similarities between mov e m e n t and deletion 129 2.1.2. The 133 (Complex) N P C o n s t r a i n t BS> xiii 2.2. 2.1.3. The W H - i s l a n d C o n s t r a i n t 2.1.4. The S e n t e n t i a l S u b j e c t C o n s t r a i n t 139 2.1.5. The T e n s e d S C o n d i t i o n 141 E f f e c t s o n the t h e o r y 2.2.1. - 137 2.2.2. 2.2. 3. 149 Subjacency 149 Binding Conditions 154 The B o u n d i n g C o n d i t i o n ( K o s t e r 1978 b ) 162 2.2.4. A p r o p o s a l by Z w a r t s (1978) 167 2.2.5. 174 Subjacency reformulated 2.2 . 5 . 1 . P a r a m e t e r s o f S u b j a c e n c y 175 T he c h o i c e of c y c l i c n o d e s 175 The n u m b e r of c y c l i c n o d e s 177 T he p o s i t i o n o f the c y c l i c boundaries ' 2.2.5.2. Strict Subjacency 2.2 . 5 . 3 . The i n t e r a c t i o n o f G a p p i n g and WH-movement 178 180 185 3. C o n c l u s i o n s 188 F o o t n o t e s to c h a p t e r 3 191 BIBLIOGRAPHY 195 INDEX 203 CHAPTER 1. The Syntax of Coordination T h i s c h a p t e r s u p p o r t s the e x i s t e n c e of s o m e c o o r d i n a t i o n rules and denies the existence considers coordination so-called "initial" s ented. This of and of o t h ers. constituents. "non-initialH description is shown Th e A first description coordination to part giv e is of pre substance to s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d d i s t i n c t i o n s w i t h i n S- an d V P - s t r u c t u r e s . The second part rules of claimed Gapping to dinations. t io n considers an third Hypothesis reviews and give The coordination and nonconstituents. Backward Conjunction exhaustive description part the reconsiders Phrasal the p r e v i o u s l y p r o p o s e d Reduction, of The Reduction of suc h the S e n t e n c e are coor Conjunc Conjunction Hypothesis, and r u les o f F o r w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n Le f t P e r i p h e r a l D e l e t i o n a n d C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t . is s h o w n that It t h ese r u l e s are s u p e r f l u o u s g i v e n the p r o p o s e d f o r m u l a t i o n o f the rule of G apping. 1. P H R A S A L C O N J U N C T I O N : I N I T I A L VS. N O N - I N I T I A L C O O R D I N A T I O N 1 Superficially, called initial the difference and non-initial in the n u m b e r of c o o r d i n a t o r s : conjunct dination, is (Throughout w ill be preceded the by a coordinator; this monograph, semantic parallels e x a m p l e s w i l l be c l e a r e v e n Dutch before. In t h ose is not. the in what is here is a d i f f e r e n c e in i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n , leftmost conjunct not transparent, between coordination English mo s t in n o n - i n i t i a l Compare a nd cases. eac h coor (1) a n d (2). Dutch Often, examples the Dutch to t h ose w h o n e v e r s a w a w o r d of cases where the Dutch examples a li t e r a l t r a n s l a t i o n w i l l be g i v e n . ) are - 2 - (1) I n i tial C o o r d i n a t i o n a. b o t h J o h n a n d Bob a n d Bill en J a n en B o b e n Bill b. e i t h e r J o h n or Bob or Bill of J a n o f Bob of Bill (2) M o n - i n i t i a l C o o r d i n a t i o n a. J o h n (and) Bob a n d Bill Jan (en) Bob en Bill b. J o h n (or) B ob or Bill J a n (of) B ob of Bill In i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n s c a n be f o r m e d by- c o o r d i n a t o r s such as: (in E n g l i s h : ) (in Du t c h : ) both e n ... en ... ... a nd ... e i t h e r ... o r ... o f ... o f neither noch Non-initial ... n or ... ... ... n o c h ... c o o r d i n a t i o n s c a n be f o r m e d b y c o o r d i n a t o r s such as a n d , o r , n o r in E n g l i s h a nd en, of, n o c h in Dutch. There of initial English is an i n t e r e s t i n g vs. and non-initial Dutch allow difference in the d i s t r i b u t i o n s coordinations. non-initial In m a x i m a l p r o j e c t i o n s as well as for m a j o r p h r a s e s , (4), whereas initial coordination general coordinations is p r o j e c t i o n s o f the l e x i c a l c a t e g o r y only, allowed cf. cf. for a. N P : a small bu s or a b i g c a r ee n k l e i n e b us o f een g r o t e a u t o b. P P : on o ur p l a t e s n o r in o u r c u p s op onze b o r d e n n o c h in o n z e k o p j e s e r g r o o d en e rg b l a u w both non (3) a n d maximal (5) and (6). (3) N o n - i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n o f the m a j o r p h r a s e c. AP: v e r y r ed a n d v e r y blue for - 3 - d. VP: t h a t he w i l l e at a n d w i l l d r i n k dat hi j zal e t e n en zal d r i n k e n (4) M o n - i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n o f the l e x i c a l c a t e g o r y a. N; a small bus or c ar e en k l e i n e b us o f auto b. P: rig h t a b o v e or b e n e a t h that l i t t l e ch e s t v l a k b o v e n o f o n d e r dat k l e i n e k a s t j e c. A: v e r y red a n d blue e r g r o o d en b l a u w d. V: t h a t he w i l l e at a n d d r i n k dat hij zal e t e n en d r i n k e n (5) I n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n o f the m a j o r p h r a s e a, N P : e i t h e r a small b us o r a b i g car o f e en k l e i n e b us o f e e n g r o t e a u t o b, PP: n e i t h e r on o u r p l a t e s n o r in o u r c u p s . n o c h op o n z e b o r d e n n o c h in o n z e k o p j e s c. A P : n e i t h e r v e r y r ed n o r v e r y b l u e noch erg rood noch erg blauw d. VP: that he n e i t h e r d id eat n o r w i l l eat dat hij n o c h h e e f t g e g e t e n n o c h zal e t e n (6) I n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n o f the l e x i c a l c a t e g o r y (with the a p p a r e n t e x c e p t i o n o f the E n g l i s h ve r b ) a. N: a small e i t h e r bus o r c a r * e e n k l e i n e of b u s o f auto b. P: * ri g h t e i t h e r a b o v e or b e n e a t h t h a t l i t t l e ch e s t * v l a k of b o v e n of o n d e r dat k l e i n e k a s t j e c. A: * v e r y b o t h r ed a n d blue * e rg zowel r o o d a l s b l a u w d. V: that he will b o t h eat a n d d r i n k d at hij zal e n e t e n en d r i n k e n This regularity lexical appears categories such to as be f a l s i f i e d by c o o r d i n a t i o n s of (7) and (8), for which super * - 4 - ficially both non-initial and initial coordination is g r a m matical . (7) N o n - i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n of the l e x i c a l c a t e g o r y a. N: s o n g s an d s t o r i e s abou t g h o s t s l i e d e r e n en v e r h a l e n o v e r s p o k e n b. P: in o r on the chest in o f op de kast c. A: g r e e n o r red w i t h w h i t e d o t s g r o e n o f r ood m e t w i t t e s t i p p e n d. V: tha t he c a l l e d n o r w r o t e to h i s l o v e r dat hi j b e l d e n o c h s c h r e e f n a a r z i j n l i e f j e (8) ( A p p a r e n t ) i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n o f the l e x i c a l categorie a. N: b o t h s o n g s and s t o r i e s a b o u t g h o s t s e n l i e d e r e n en v e r h a l e n o v e r s p o k e n b. P: • e i t h e r in o r on the chest of in o f op de kast c. A: e i t h e r g r e e n or red w i t h w h i t e d o t s of g r o e n o f r o o d met w i t t e s t i p p e n d. V: that he n e i t h e r c a l l e d n o r w r o t e to h i s l o v e r dat hij n o c h b e l d e n o c h s c h r e e f n a a r zijn l i e f j e It is d i f f i c u l t to a c c o u n t for the u n g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of (6) if one assumes generated fore, as tha t the coordinations initial coordinations it s e e m s m o r e reasonable in o f N, to d e r i v e (8) are directly P, A a n d V. (8) t r a n s f o r m a t i o n a l l y as i n d i c a t e d in (9). (9) a. NP: b o t h s o n g s and s t o r i e s a b o u t ghosts en l i e d e r e n spoken There en v e r h a l e n o v e r b. PP: e i t h e r in fM é / é V ié é t o r on the c h e s t of in ié / V ié -é i o f op de kast c. A P : e i t h e r g r e e n '¿¿.fit or r e d w i t h w h i t e d ots of g r o e n of r o o d m et w i t t e stippen H d. VP: t h a t he n e i t h e r c a l l e d f - it / V it é / t é f é f n o r w r o t e to h i s l o v e r dat hij n o e h b e l d e noch s c h r e e f n a a r z i j n liefj e No such 'final part' deletion could have generated the s e n t e n c e s o f (6) f r o m i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n s o f m a j o r p h r a s e s , since in the e x a m p l e s o f (6) the c o o r d i n a t e d n o d e s t h e m s e l v e s are final. richer Under underlying coordination ions of ture, the assumption structure, obeys that the (8) derives distribution a well-defined pattern: bu t nonmaximal projections may of maximal a c a t e g o r y m a y f u n c t i o n as c o n j u n c t s from in i t i a l project in d e e p not. The a struc apparent e x c e p t i o n o f V in E n g l i s h in (6) will be d i s c u s s e d below. In view specific of the advantage g r a m m a t i c a l ity to be d e r i v a t i o n of n o n - i n i t i a l sume that non-initial gained of from conjunctions. coordinations (4), the are t here is no transformational I will therefore as generated directly ( c f . s e c t i o n 3.1.). The resulting distribution of initial and non-initial c o o r d i n a t i o n s m a y be s u m m a r i z e d b y the p h r a s e s t r u c t u r e rule s c h e m a t a (10) a n d (11) (C s t a n d s f o r c o o r d i n a t o r ) : (10) N o n - i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n X ------> X (C X ) n , fo r a n y c h o i c e 2 of X (11) I n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n X ------ s»C X (C X)n , where X is an abbreviation of "m a x i m a l p r o j e c t i o n o f a c a t e g o r y " . These rule schemata s t r u c t u r e rules, abbreviate infinite as in (10') a n d ( 1 1 ’): sets of phrase • - 6 X --- > X X ----> X c X c X c X X ----> X c X c X c X etc . c X c X c X c X c X c X c Xt X C X X --- » X --- > X ----- > etc . Th e r e does is one not p r o p e r t y of i n i t i a l follow briefly here, further study. from the schema although its Compare the coordination in (11). I will explanation English w ill and ( 1 2 ): in D u t c h describe have Dutch that to it await examples in ' (12) a. The o r i g i n o f e i t h e r h e a v e n o r e a r t h is unk n o w n . *He t o n t s t a a n v a n o f de h e m e l of de a a r d e is onbekend. b. ' N e a r e i t h e r the i n s t i t u t e or the c h u r c h is a lunch r o o m . * Bij o f he t i n s t i t u u t of de k e r k is een cafetari a . c. The a n s w e r s bot h of M a r y a nd of J o h n s u r p r i s e d him. * De a n t w o o r d e n en v a n M a r i e en v a n J a n v e r r a s t e n hem. In E n g l i s h m a x i m a l p r o j e c t i o n s , cal position, D utch, on dominated form only maximal by possible coordination. S or VP These are constituents of coordinators seems to behave speakers of matical : are (cf. H a n k a m e r 1973, pair a l s . .., most initial the o t h e r hand, major constituents One in no m a t t e r w h i c h h i e r a r c h i grammatical Dutch, l ike the in the coordinations. In projections directly conjuncts usually of a i nitial referred to as 18). Dutch, English following the pair zowel... coordinators. examples are For gram (13) a. De a n t w o o r d e n zo w e l v a n M a r i e als v a n Jan v e r r a s t e n hem, (The a n s w e r s b o t h of M a r i e a n d o f J o h n s u r p r i s e d him) b. Hij spr a k m et zov/el J a n als Piet. (He sp o k e to b o t h J o h n a n d P e t e r ) Observe that expressed rules by being Dutch phrase of fact major structure position examples w h ic h , h o w e v e r , The notion context-free, hierarchical the the of in rule there the (12) constituency (11): is n o inp u t pose phrase way node. a cannot to structure refer This problem, to implies a be the that solution of c a n n o t be o f f e r e d here. that in i t i a l coordination appears in major p h r a s e s e x c l u s i v e l y c a n a l s o be u s e d as a d i a g n o s t i c m e a n s of determining phrasal constituency. In p a r t i c u l a r , this m e c h a n ism c an be e m p l o y e d t o w a r d s the d e m o n s t r a t i o n t h a t D u t c h w o r d order is underlyingly below, in s e c t i o n 1.1., V P - s t r u c t u r e s . In SOV. This point will be developed in a c o m p a r i s o n o f D u t c h a n d E n g l i s h section 1.2. I wil l then briefly compare Dutch and English S - s t r u c t u r e s . 1.1. VP S T R U C T U R E S A N D U N D E R L Y I N G S O V In Dutch subordinate clau s e s , all verbs are final, a l t h o u g h t h e y m a y be f o l l o w e d by S- or P P - c o n s t i t u e n t s , as in (14) : (14) a. ..., dat hij t u l p e n zal p l a n t e n (that he t u l i p s will p l a n t ) b, dat hij t u l p e n zal p l a n t e n in z i j n v o o r t u i n (that he t u l i p s w i l l p l a n t in h i s f r o n t g a r d e n ) c. ..., dat hij de t u l p e n zal planter, d i e hij h e e f t gekregen (that he the t u l i p s w i l l p l a n t w h i c h he h a s got) f - 8 - In m a i n c l a u s e s , finite verbs usua l l y obtain second position. All n o n - f i n i t e v e r b s o b e y the p a t t e r n o b s e r v e d in (14). (15) a. Hij zal t u l p e n p l a n t e n . (He w i l l t u l i p s p l a n t ) b . Hij zal t u l p e n p l a n t e n in z i j n v o o r t u i n . (He w i l l t u l i p s p l a n t in his fr o n t g a r d e n ) c. Hij zal de t u l p e n p l a n t e n die hij heeft g e k r e g e n . (He w i l l the t u l i p s p l a n t w h i c h he h a s got) Thus, disregarding Dutch subordinate extraposition of S- and clauses display SOV word PP-constituents, ord e r , w h i l e m a i n c l a u s e s h a v e S Y O order. No t unexpectedly, the r e h as been some debate recently a m o n g l i n g u i s t s c o n c e r n e d w i t h D u t c h s y n t a x w h e t h e r to d e r i v e the s u b o r d i n a t e derive the clauses main f r o m S VO o r d e r b y V - p o s t p o s i n g or to clause from an SOV order by V - p r e posing. S u r v e y s o f the r e s p e c t i v e a r g u m e n t s p r o a n d c o n are p r e s e n t e d in K o s t e r (1975) underlying a nd T h i e r s c h order. coordination (1978). basis of They both the behavior take of c a n be c o n s t r u c t e d f o r the 3 VP-phrase, clauses in i t i a l not w i t h i n coordination the v e r b a l complex is p o s s i b l e itself, (16) a nd (16'): (16) S O V as i n i tial The a r g u m e n t r u n s as f o l l o w s . In s u b o r d i n a t e the the in D u t c h a n a r g u m e n t same p o s i t i o n . on On a. O m d a t J a n en [ypde r o z e n snoeit] en [ypde t u l p e n p l a n t ] ,... (Because J a n b o t h the r o s e s p r u n e s a n d the t u l i p s pl a n t s , b. O m d a t J a n en ...) [ypde r o z e n zal s n o eien] en [ypde t u l p e n zal p l a n t e n ] , . . . ( B e c a u s e J a n b o t h the r o s e s w i l l p r u n e a n d the t u l i p s w i l l plant, ...) cf. r - 9 - (16') O m d a t J a n de r o z e n zal e n [^.planten] en ■ [ysnoeien] , ... (B e c a u s e Ja n the r oses will b o t h p l a n t a n d p r u n e , ..,) P r o j e c t i o n s o f V in s u b o r d i n a t e c l a u s e s t hus o b e y the g e n e r a l pattern of init i a l coordinations, coordinations: VPs may form i nitial bu t Vs m a y not. N o w c o n s i d e r m a i n c l a u s e v a r i a n t s of (16): (17) a. * J a n en s n o e i t de r o z e n en p l a n t de t ulpen. (Jan b o t h p r u n e s the r o s e s a n d p l a n t s the tulips) b. * Ja n en zal de r o z e n s n o e i e n en zal de t u l p e n pl a n t e n . (Jan b o t h w i l l the r o s e s p r u n e a n d w i l l the t u l i p s plant) (17') J a n zal en de r o z e n s n o e i e n en de t u l p e n p l a n t e n , (Jan w i l l b o t h the r o s e s p r u n e a n d the t u l i p s p l a n t ) From the c r i t e r i a for t ion 1 (plus it nonfinite whereas be follows i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n d e v e l o p e d in s e c that in v erb) are (17) finite no t together object NP plus nonfinite verb anticipated is the verb if (18) fit to c a r r y i n i t i a l plus object NP one constituent, in (17') are. T h i s c an surface structure of main and there clauses. VP is is no a phrase constituent daughters of VP to under m a t i c a l l y of (17), vs. unite one the label. coordination, finite This verb explains and the the g r a m m a t i c a l i t y o f (17'). other ungram m - 10 - Compare (18) with (18'). A s s h o w n b y (16), the structure of s u b o r d i n a t e clauses in s u b o r d i n a t e c l a u s e s all v e r b s are u n i t e d u n d e r VP. (18' ) D u t c h V P - s t r u e t u r e in s u b o r d i n a t e c l a u s e s Structures (18) which moves and (18') presuppose the f i n i t e v e r b a Verb Fronting rule out of the V P , i n m a i n c l a u s e s as follows: ( 18" ) Verb Fronting Thus the SOV-structure of subordinate clauses underlies the s u p e r f i c i a l SVO o r d e r o f m a i n c l a uses. By c o n t r a s t , which verb and if one a s s u m e s object ar e an u n d e r l y i n g S V O o rder, members e x p l a n a t i o n s follow. Examples of VP (see (19)), in no ' (17) w ill h ave to be e x c l u d e d b y the ad hoc s t i p u l a t i o n that Dutch, quite unlike English, r e q u i r e s the i m m e d i a t e - 11 - c o n t i g u i t y of the V P - d o m i n a t e d V and the l e f t m o s t c o n s t i t u e n t o f the s e n t e n c e . A d d i t i o n a l l y , it r e m a i n s a m y s t e r y w h y (17') is g r a m m a t i c a l . Given underlying with an initial rule of V e r b the finite the verbs will be main clauses d e r i v e d b y the in an a c r o s s - t h e - b o a r d m a n n e r , w h e r e b y of all*’c o n j u n c t s are moved out of the T h i s is s c h e m a t i z e d in (20): the a c r o s s - t h e - b o a r d m o v e m e n t finite obligatory coordination of VPs Fronting coordination. Obviously, S O V w o r d - o r d e r f o r Dutch, verbs rule, are i d e ntical. there Sinc e is p o s s i b l e Verb o n l y if Fronting is no m a i n c l a u s e v a r i a n t 4 of is an (21) in w h i c h the f i n i t e v e r b s differ: (21) ..., dat J a n of wint of v e r l i e s t . (..., (22) * that J a n e i t h e r w i n s or loses) J a n of w i n t of verliest. (Jan e i t h e r w i n s or loses) In E n g l i s h , ordinate the clauses distribution of verbs obeys SVO-order in m a i n a n d s u b throughout, and initial c o o r d i n a t i o n of v e r b a l p h r a s e s d i s p l a y s i d e n t i c a l p a t t e r n s in main as well as subordinate clauses (see Dougherty 865-7): (23) a. J o h n n e i t h e r did eat nor will eat. b. ..., that J o h n n e i t h e r d i d eat n o r w i l l eat. 1970, I - 12 - (24) a, J o h n b o t h ate soup a n d d r a n k beer. b. These ..., that J o h n b o t h ate soup a n d d r a n k beer. examples suggest that A u x a n d VP are t o g e t h e r one c o n stituent. It f o l l o w s that the s e n t e n t i a l s t r u c t u r e in E n g l i s h is in (25), than (26), as 1977, 48). as as p r o p o s e d b y D o u g h e r t y proposed by, e.g., (1971, Jackendoff 315), (1972, rather 76; and (26) (25) NP VP. AUX Furthermore, NP the hitherto anomalous AUX initial VP coordinations s uch as (27) a. J o h n w i l l b o t h p r u n e the r o s e s a n d p l a n t the tulips. b. J o h n d i d n e i t h e r w i n nor lose. which disobey its Aux the internal the p a t t e r n o f constituent structure of VPs (29), p r o p o s e d b y S ag (1976, Only if b o t h VP s examples of dinations, (27) but in (28) obey this (6), suggest that a VP w i t h o u t m a y f u n c t i o n as a m a x i m a l the can is (28) rather phrase. Thus, than structure 264): are c a l l e d m a x i m a l p r o j e c t i o n s , general hardly be pattern of taken into initial account the coor as a s e r i o u s s o l u tion. Under this a n a l y s i s o f E n g l i s h a n d D u t c h VP s t r u c t u r e s , the g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of the c o m p a r a b l e c o o r d i n a t i o n s in (30) is e x p l a i n e d d i f f e r e n t l y in b o t h lan g u a g e s . r - 13 - (30) J o h n wi l l b o t h s i n g a song and d a n c e a jig. ( D o u g h e r t y 1970, 865) Ja n zal en een li e d z i n g e n en e e n t a n g o d a n sen. For E n g l i s h , sing a song their the a n a l y s i s p r e s e n t e d a b o v e c l a i m s tha t the V P s and d a n c e a jig derivation, are whereas for maximal Dutch, phrases it is throughout claimed that een l i e d z i n g e n a n d een t a n g o d a n s e n a re V P s o u t of w h i c h the finite verb description implies a (z a l ) of crucial o n l y one verb, VP and Dutch has the prediction. it wi l l to c o n s t r u e (cf. been (31b) removed seemingly be across-the-board. parallel structures Thi s in (30) If the u n d e r l y i n g VP c o n t a i n s possible to p r e p o s e it out of its a n i n i t i a l V P - c o o r d i n a t i o n w i t h o u t a V in and (d) ) . S i m i l a r cases in (31a) a n d ( c )) are c l a i m e d to be u n g r a m m a t i c a l . English (cf. The f a c t s are e x a c t l y as p r e d i c t e d . (31) a. Jo h n g a v e b o t h M a r y an a p p l e a n d P e t e r a pear. b. c. J a n g a f en M a r i e een a p p e l en P i e t e e n peer. * J o h n ga v e e i t h e r an a p p l e to M a r y or a p e a r to P e t e r d. Jan g a f of e e n a p p e l a a n M a r i e of e e n p e e r aan Piet. 1.2. S S T R U C T U R E S As may form argued above, initial maximal p r o j e c t i o n s of N, coordinations. c o o r d i n a t i o n s o f S: A, Let us n o w c o n s i d e r P, and V i n i tial - / x (32) a. * 14 - . He r e g r e t s the f act e i t h e r t h a t S u s a n m u s t leave f or A f r i c a or tha t M a r y m u s t l eave f o r E urope. Hij b e t r e u r t h e t f e i t of dat S u s a n n a a r A f r i k a g a a t of dat M a r y n a a r E u r o p a gaat. (He r e g r e t s the f act e i t h e r that S u s a n to A f r i c a g o e s or t hat M a r y to E u r o p e g o e s . ) b. * I am l o o k i n g for s o m e o n e e i t h e r w h o l i v e s n e a r b y o r w h o still g o e s to scho o l . * Ik z o e k i e m a n d of die dic h t bij w o o n t of die n o g op s c h o o l zit. (I l o o k for s o m e o n e e i t h e r w h o n e a r b y l i v e s o r w h o s t i l l to s c h o o l goes) c. * The d i f f i c u l t y e i t h e r f o r P e t e r to b u y f o o d or f o r J o h n to c o o k d i n n e r is n o t o b v i o u s . H e t b e z w a a r o f om e t e n te k o p e n of om e t e n te k o k e n rnaakt g e e n indruk. (The d i f f i c u l t y e i t h e r f o r f o o d to b u y or f o r f o o d to c o o k m a k e s n o i m p r e s s i o n ) (33) a. He r e g r e t s the f a c t that e i t h e r S u s a n m u s t leave f o r A f r i c a o r M a r y m u s t l e a v e for E u r o p e . Hi j b e t r e u r t he t f e i t dat of S u s a n n a a r A f r i k a g a a t of M a r y n a a r E u r o p a gaat. b. I am l o o k i n g for s o m e o n e w h o e i t h e r l i v e s n e a r by or still g o e s to school. Ik z o e k i e m a n d die of dic h t bíj w o o n t of n o g op s c h o o l zit. c, o 'The d i f f i c u l t y fo r e i t h e r P e t e r to b u y f o o d or J o h n to c o o k d i n n e r is no t obv i o u s . H e t b e z w a a r om en e t e n te k o p e n en e t e n te k o k e n rnaakt g e e n indruk. Minor projections coordinations, of S as in an d m a x i m a l (33), form grammatical projections of S as in in i t i a l (32), do - 15 - not. According izers are to related are related are inseparable t e nces. be some to to n o uns. Thus an in i t i a l opposite (32) in the theory, same complement way determiners It s h o u l d f o l l o w that c o m p l e m e n t i z e r s from the e x p e cted: version of X-bar sentences coordination of bare pattern of grammaticalities sen is to is to be as g r a m m a t i c a l as e i t h e r the b o y s or the g i r l s , a nd (33) as ’u n g r a m m a t i c a l as the e i t h e r b o y s or g i r l s . Apart f r o m this, er al reasons. First, tion between S and (32) and observe S'. (33) that This are i n t e r e s t i n g f o r s e v they confirm distinction is the d i s t i n c motivated for E n g l i s h s e n t e n c e s by the f o l l o w i n g e x a m p l e s in B r e s n a n (1974, 618): - (34) a. I c a n tell y o u w h e n , b u t I c a n ' t tell y o u w h y he left me. Ik k an je v e r t e l l e n w a n n e e r maar ik k a n je n i e t v e r t e l l e n w a a r o m hij me v e r l i e t . b. I've b e e n w o n d e r i n g w h e t h e r b ut w o u l d n ' t p o s i t i v e l y w a n t to s t a t e that, y o u r t h e o r y is correct, Ik v r o e g m e wel af o f I i i i i i f , /i &, maar I ik k on niet b e v e s t i g e n dat j o u w t h e o r i e jui s t is. The type of deletion displayed Conjunction constituent Reduction. only In in (34) is a c a s e of B a c k w a r d English, this rule deletes (see s e c t i o n 2 .2..SL. b e l o w ) , -and c o n s e q u e n t ly, the e x a m p l e s in (34) p r o v i d e e v i d e n c e f o r s t r u c t u r e (35) one (35): _,S' comp" In Dutch, B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n is not r e s t r i c t e d so as to d e l e t e s t r i n g s w h i c h t o g e t h e r are one c o n s t i t u e n t only. Therefore, motivate the Dutch examples of (34) cannot the c o n s t i t u e n c y of the s h a d e d s t r i n g . be used to The e x a m p l e s - 16 - in (33) show, however, r e l e v a n t to Dutch, determining following structure (35) is in some way as well. Furthermore, in tha t the the examples observed categorial suggest distinction status that of might main declaratives be helpful clauses. The are S, w h e r e a s q u e s t i o n s are S ’: (36) a. E i t h e r it r a i n s or the s u n is shini n g . Of h e t r e g e n t of de z o n s c h i j n t . b. E i t h e r y o u w i n o r y o u los e ( D o u g h e r t y 1971, 315) Of je w i n t of je verli e s t . (37) a. * E i t h e r doe s it r a i n or is the s u n s h i n i n g ? * 0 f r e g e n t h e t of s c h i j n t de zon? b. E i t h e r w h o w i n s or w h o l o s e s ? * However, beyond O f w i e w i n t of w i e v e r l i e s t ? the the implications scope of the of these present observations stud y , and lie will well no t be f u r t h e r p u r s u e d here. 2. C O O R D I N A T I O N S O F N O N C O N S T I T U E N T S In general coordinations cannot the be of phrase structure constituents. generated coordinations. unless Here the The rules can following shaded parts (38) and (39) generate only sentences thus are i n c l u d e d in incorporate bas e c o n j u n c t i o n s o f S: (38) M a x s a i d that J o h n a t e an a p p l e a n d P e t e r a pear. M a x zei dat J a n e e n a p pel at e n P i e t e e n p e e r (39) M a x s a i d that J o h n b o u g h t I , a n d P e t e r ate an apple. M a x zei dat J a n een a p pel en P e t e r e e n p e e r at. r _ (38) is an instance of 17 _ forward reduction: junct f o l l o w s the full c o n j u n c t , ward reduction: the reduced the reduced con (39) is an i n s t a n c e of b a c k conjunct precedes the full con junct , The f a c t s of c o o r d i n a t i o n r e d u c t i o n c o n t r i b u t e to one of the earliest (see arguments Chomsky, worked out 1957, since, fo r underlying 3 5 ^ ff.). an d the Several most syntactic structures proposals interesting of have been these are b r i e f l y s u m m a r i z e d in (40): (40) R O S S & L A K O F F (see R o s s 1967) 1. F o r w a rd C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n a n d B a c k w a r d Conjunction Reduction (rules o f l e f t p e r i p h e r a l a nd r ight p e r i p h e r a l deletion,' f o r m u l a t e d t o g e t h e r as one m i r r o r - i m a g e rule) 2. G a p p i n g ( d e l e t e s verbs, b a c k w a r d in s o m e l a n g u a g e s and f o r w a r d in o t h e r s ; the d i r e c t i o n is d e t e r m i n e d b y the s t r u c t u r a l p o s i t i o n o f the v e r b ) TAI , (1969) A rule of D e l e t i o n only, w h i c h a p p l i e s f o r w a r d and backward; the d i r e c t i o n is d e t e r m i n e d b y the s t r u c t u r a l p o s i t i o n o f the d e l e t i o n site, HANKAMER (1971) 1* D e l e t i o n , a g e n e r a l f o r w a r d d e l e t i n g rule, w h i c h e f f e c t u a t e s i n t e r n a l an d p e r i p h e r a l d e l e t i o n . 2, D e l a y , right p e r i p h e r a l d e l e t i o n . S A G (1976) 1. G a p p i n g , f o r w a r d d e l e t i o n o f i n t e r n a l a n d r i g h t p e r i p h e r a l parts. 2. R i g h t M o d e R a i s i n g , a r i g h t p e r i p h e r a l d e l e t i o n , s i m i l a r to B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n . 3. Left P e r i p h e r a l D e l e t i o n , s i m i l a r to F o r w a r d Conjunction Reduction. In this tio n c h a p t e r we w i l l reduction rules: s h o w the n e c e s s i t y of t w o c o o r d i n a a forward deletion rule (Gapping, I - 18 - e x e m p l i f i e d in Conjunction be and a backward Reduction, presented another (38)), to that the exemplified these extent rules that it in differ is of 2.1., Gapping. but subsection deals of Section with 2.1. 2.2. Backward and 2.2. is (39)). (Backward Arguments drastically completely c o l l a p s e them into one rule schema. rule deletion rule will from one impossible to S e c t i o n 2.1. c o n c e r n s the structured analogously Conjunction concentrates Reduction. on a to Each difference b e t w e e n G a p p i n g and B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n . T h i s p r e c e d e s the d i s c u s s i o n o f s e c t i o n 3, w h e r e it wi l l be argued exhaust th e s e that the rules, Gapping number no of and Backward Conjunction coordination reduction further rules are involved Reduction rules. in the Next to coordina ti o n r e d u c t i o n p h e n o m e n o n . 2.1, G A P P I N G In this section I will discuss the f o l l o w i n g t h e o r e t i c a l l y m o s t i m p o r t a n t c h a r a c t e r i s t i c s o f the rule of G apping: (a) its r e m n a n t s are m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s ; (b) it is a v a r i a b l e - c h a n g i n g rule; (c) it is a m u l t i p l e - t a r g e t rule; (d) the rule is i s l a n d - s e n s i t i v e ; (e) its d o m a i n s are S', S, and VP; (f) a n d the rule m a y a p p l y a c r o s s - t h e - b o a r d . A (preliminary) formulation e n d of t h i s section. of Gapping is presented at the I - 19 - 2.1.1. M A J O R C O N S T I T U E N C Y C o n s i d e r the s e n t e n c e s in (41). (41) C h a r l e y w r i t e s w i t h a p e n c i l a nd J o h n w i t h a pen. a pen. l i i t p s l i l pen. * K a r e l schrij ft me t e e n p o t l o o d en J o h n met e e n pen. * é ’t i ï t i i f t / t i é t e e n pen. pen. h ft/ M t M i i These examples s h o w t hat G a p p i n g d o e s not d e l e t e s u b p a r t s of major constituents ( H a n k a m e r 1973, 18). 2.1.2. V A R I A B L E S AS T A R G E T S FO R D E L E T I O N O R INTERPRETATION It is g e n e r a l l y a s s u m e d change constituents function call as this section it only, contexts principle wil l be an d (see, the that Obviously, is transformational a true the rule, 1976, that only Let us In of Gapping is e i t h e r or may 312). condition'. r ule consequence r u l e s can variables Chomsky 'constituent variables. no t transformational that e.g., shown the that this deletes that G a p p i n g transformational r u l e s are n o t c o n s t r a i n e d so as to c h a n g e c o n s t i t u e n t s only. From the constituent string deleted by Gapping grammatical gapped condition f o r m s one variants of (42) e nce of the c i r c l e d V P - n o d e s in (43); it follows constituent. that the The v a r i o u s t h e r e b y s h o w the exist ? - 20 (42) I w a n t to try to b e g i n to w r i t e a n o v e l a n d you to t r y to b e g i n to w r i t e a play, isHit11<j>! t f i to b e g i n to w r i t e a play. to w r i t e a play. I iii-iht ! H I t t i ! t i ¡ M t H I M I ' k f i t i a play. (Ross 1970, 250) Apart from Gapping, however, any known rule incompatible in s t a n c e Gapping, of with proposed VP-deletion, this rul e structure grammar. (43) is u n s u p p o r t e d b y Moreover, analyses this o f the VP. a rul e no t a v a i l a b l e optionally results in structure is C o n s i d e r for in D u t c h . J u s t as different output strings: ( 4 4 ) i w a n t to try to begin- to w r i t e a n o v e l , but you don't wa n t to m i u m m i u i u m i é - i u a i . w a n t to t r y to M i U I U l i i H U I A / M M t . wa n t to t r y to b e g i n to it f f t i ! V P - d e l e t i o n thus of (45): s h o w s the existence . of the c i r c l e d V P - n o d e s I - 21 want The c o m b i n a t i o n o f (45) a n d (43) le a d s to the f o l l o w i n g p a r a doxical are constituent shown to structure, exist by in Gapping, which a nd the the A-constituents B-constituents are s h o w n to e x i s t b y V P - d e l e t i o n : (46) y o u do n ' t [R [ L [. L want]. B1 A4 A3 A2 A 1 [g b e g i n ] A to to L try] 1 [g write] A to 2 2 a novel] B4 B3 B 2 B 1 (or, o m i t t i n g some b r a c k e t s : ) [A w a n t to If Gapping were c o u l d no l o n g e r be ce. It is interprets t h is shown variable, a constituent one, generally are chapter that the Stillings constituent Gapping However, interpreted 2, deleting A a novel] rule, B„ VP-deletion o b v i o u s l y an u n a c c e p t a b l e c o n s e q u e n agreed non-constituents. position in [g t ry to b e g i n to write] in the various assumes variable, either consequences ways. that should deletes a be or of As will be new kind of added to the ff - 22 - inventory of descriptive means transformational rules. Fiengo transformational rule, but a available assumes ru l e discussed assume for that in the deletion chapter 2: expressing that G a p p i n g of is no t a interpretation, a p p l i e s to n o n - c o n s t i t u e n t s . A n d o t h e r s be for which (whose p r o p o s a l s will H a n k a m e r , L a n g e n d o e n , and constituent condition transformations. All simply authors does Sag), not hol d therefore agree that a le s s r e s t r i c t e d t h e o r y s h o u l d be d e v e l o p e d in o r d e r to c o v e r the G a p p i n g data. 2 .1.3. M U L T I P L E T A R G E T D E L E T I O N Gapping sentences, cf. deletes discontiguous parts of coordinated (47): (47) a. B e t s y b e l i e v e d P e t e r to be sexy, a n d A l a n B a r b a r a t<t/i>4 / é ii- f ■ (Sag 1976, 223) b. Ti m e w a n t e d U d a l l to get the n o m i n a t i o n , Newsweek Carter f (Sag 1976, 4 / ¿ i an d t • 223) c. o m d a t K a r e l v o o r g e s t e l d heef't m o s s e l e n te b e s t e l l e n en H a r r i e oesters til'éiitittiii(since K a r e l p r o p o s e d has m u s s e l s to o r d e r a nd Harrie oysters H / d. o m d a t K a r e l v a n p l a n is e e n b o o t te k o p e n en Harrie een kampeerauto U l U i U - (since K a r e l p l a n s has a b o a t to b u y a n d H a r r i e a camper These examples strings. show It f o l l o w s accepted constraint, that Gapping deletes th a t G a p p i n g v i o l a t e s the constraint discontiguous a second generally tha t o n l y on e t a r g e t m a y be i n v o l v e d in a t r a n s f o r m a t i o n a l rule. 2.1.4. that the ISLAND SENSITIVITY The key the variable first various observation to n o t i c e island constrain (48) this and the rule of is i s l a n d s e n s i t i v e . (1971, constraints deletion his examples, regarding deleted 20; "Gapping also demonstrated movement Gapping in is H a n k a m e r was Ross transformations"), obeys the (1967) to although g i v e n h e r e in (48) are e x t r e m e l y u n f o r t u n a t e . a. C o o r d i n a t e S t r u c t u r e C o n s t r a i n t : A l f o n s e c o o k e d the rice, a n d H a r r y and ate t he beans. b . Sentential Subject Constraint : ÿ A l f o n s e a te the rice, a nd that H a r r y the b e a n s is fant a s t i c . c . C o m p l e x NP C o n s t r a i n t : * A l f o n s e a te the rice, fact that H a r r y These the examples island cas es) do no t conditions, disappears. remnants of What Gapping a nd I w a s s t u n n e d b y the the beans. show that since the variables deleted o n l y one c o n s t i t u e n t these examples do show is s h o u l d be m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s , obey (V in all that the a n d it is this c o n d i t i o n on the r e m n a n t s w h i c h e x c l u d e s (48). F r o m this point of why Hankamer v e s t i g a t e the m a t t e r m o r e t h o r o u g h l y . - The view one understands Island Constraints variables. Since Gapping themselves restrict deletes variables, did not in the s c o p e of it is to e x p e c t e d that these v a r i a b l e s t h e m s e l v e s are c o n s t r a i n e d . be The r e l e v a n t c o n s t r u c t i o n s are t h e r e f o r e : (49) a. Coordinate Structure C o n straint: A l f o n s e c o o k e d the rice a n d the b e a n s a n d H a r r y “M i / t i i é / W « i the p o t a t o e s . A l f o n s k o o k t e de r i j s t e n de b o n e n en H a r r y K<ié lk t é / $ £ / t i i & t /4ii de a a r d a p p e l s . f - 24 - b. Sentential Subject C o n s t r a i n t : T hat A l f o n s e a t e the rice is f a n t a s t i c a n d i W # Harry the b e a n s H I ■ * D a t A l f o n s r i j s t at is p r a c h t i g e n Harry bonen c . C o m p l e x NP C o n s t r a i n t : * A l f o n s e d i s c u s s e d the q u e s t i o n of w h i c h r i c e we w o u l d eat a n d H a r r y 1 (o f) which beans A l f o n s b e s p r a k de v r a a g w e l k e r i j s t we z o u d e n e t e n en H a r r y $ welke bonen 4 U tiii ■ yM/ T h i s d e m o n s t r a t e s that the v a r i a b l e i n v o l v e d in G a p p i n g is in line w i t h the v a r i a b l e of o t h e r rule s o f s e n t e n c e g r a m m a r . i m p l i e s t h a t G a p ping, of language, b e l o n g s to the core of g r a m m a r . is o f the u t m o s t differs 2.1.1. is in from a n d 2.1.2. a variable the Gapping alleged Gapping 2.1.5. on rules The This observation in o t h e r r e s p e c t s G a p p i n g sentence grammar. rule than one The is of t a r g e t m a y be crucial of sentence grammar, may conditions a rule of that m o r e rules phenomena as since sections a l r e a d y r e v e a l e d that the t a r g e t o f G a p p i n g an d rule. conditions importance, other It fa r f r o m b e i n g an a d d i t i o n a l p e c u l a r i t y on of give insight these, sentence in rules. grammar relevance since the status Further will the involved to the s t u d y of of problems some for be p r e s e n t e d in a n d 2.1.6. 2.1.5. Gapping THE D O M A I N S O F G A P P I N G applies s h o w n in (50), (51), to c o o r d i n a t i o n s of S 1, S a n d VP, as is a n d (52), r e s p e c t i v e l y ; f - 25 - (50) a. Who w a n t s to i n v i t e P e t e r a n d w h o / t$ I M ary? Wi e wil P e t e r u i t n o d i g e n en wie i t f t M a r i e b. It is no t c l e a r w h i c h b o o k s are c h o s e n by Mary, and which books b y Max. I Het is n i e t d u i d e l i j k w e l k e b o e k e n d o o r M a r i e g e k o z e n z í j n en w e l k e b o e k e n d o o r M a x iï& t i. (51) a. E i t h e r J o h n k i s s e d M a r y or M a r y lk f i é é é P eter. Of Jan heeft Marie gezoend of Marie ¿ ¿ ¿ ¿ M i- Peter ' (E i t h e r J a n ha s M a r i e k i s s e d o r M a r i e )Ké4 P e t e r U U U ) b. The f act that e i t h e r J o h n w e n t to E u r o p e or P e t e r to S o u t h Africa, M M b o t h e r e d h i m a lot. ' H e t f e i t dat o f J a n n a a r E u r o p a z o u g a a n o f Peter naar Zuid A f rika zat h e m e r g dwars. (52) a. J o h n e i t h e r g a v e a b o o k to M a r y or t a bunch o f f l o w e r s to h e r s i s t e r s . J o h n h e e f t of e e n b o e k a a n M a r y g e g e v e n o f e e n b os bloemen aan haar zusjes U é é i M . b. J o h n b o t h t r i e d to p u t h i s c a r in the g a r a g e and t t u a m u t h i s bike in the barn. J a n p r o b e e r d e zowel z i j n a u t o in de g a r a g e te z e t t e n als z i j n f i e t s in het s c h u u r t j e t ü The i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t o r s in (51) an d (52) i n d i c a t e t h a t these examples in fact are c o o r d i n a t i o n s of S in the f o r m e r a n d VP in the latter. In n o n - i n i t i a l coordinations is to the impossible Gapping: b o t h VP of G a p p i n g : determine domain of s u c h as (53), it application of an d S c o o r d i n a t i o n s m a y h a v e b e e n the input ! 26 - - (53) J o h n t r i e d to tell M a r y that she w a s r i g h t a n d M a x tha t he w a s w r o n g t<i>/ t 4 t t tttii-1t< t> It< ktt M a x that he w a s wrong. M a x tha t he w a s wrong. fU titt J a n p r o b e e r d e Jo te v e r t e l l e n da t ze gelijk h a d en It m i g h t (53) I Ko I Ko t i H i f t i t t i t i da t hi] ongelijk had. I Ko t i H a - t i t t i i i dat hij ongelijk had. be concluded indicate th a t unconstrained, since th ese sentences. mechanisms that the be th i s derivations in sentence has (53). is derivations are lo g i c a l form. As V On underlying of to the only represented hand, de e p in tha t of the fact case of overly additional two structures differently is is a v a i l a b l e to follow restrict other several forms Gapping interpretation it w o u l d problematic three that an and several these at the t he different level of T h i s p o i n t r e m a i n s to be shown, h o w e v e r . shown deletes might various invented unambiguous derivations the formulation o n l y one From should lirfi dat hi] ongelijk had. by (50), (51) and (52), Gapping in c o o r d i n a t i o n s o f S ' , S or VP. lead one coordinations coordinations to of expect NPs, of APs, however, cannot Gapping in NPs be P and th a t in Q to This observation will coordinations in maintained. see m s Gapping delete of coordinations Of preferably N in PPs,; A in o f QPs. these possibilities, occur. (This rule a p p l i e s m o r e f r e e l y in E n g l i s h t h a n in D u t c h , of This, only N-Gapping as s h o w n by the u n g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of (54b).) (54) NP: a. One dog w i t h fiv e legs, a n o t h e r liver, a n d a t h i r d with a cow's w i t h n o head. E e n h o n d m e t v i j f poten, een tweede $0$$ met een k o e i e l e v e r , en een d e r d e Wfisi z o n d e r kop. f. 27 R o m e ' s d e s t r u c t i o n o f C a r t h a g e a n d the H u n ' s f i i & t t ' i i t o f Rome. * R o m e s v e r n i e t i g i n g v a n C a r t h a g o en H a n n i b a l s v a n Rome. PP: * S e v e r a l inches, ab o v e the g r o u n d a n d s e v e r a l feet s e a level. * E n k e l e c e n t i m e t e r s b o v e n de g r o n d en e n k e l e meters * zee n iveau. - , < / A w e e k ago, or a m o n t h ¿g0, he left f o r NY. E e n w e e k geleden, of ee n m a a n d g<£lé<Aéé, v e r t r o k hij n a a r NY. - AP: * A five y e a r y o u n g e r or 10 y e a r sister. * E e n v i j f j a a r j o n g e r of 10 j a a r zusje. •X* ■ f. He ran a f ew s e c o n d s f a s t e r or a f e w m i n u t e s to h i s house. » Hij liep e n k e l e s e c o n d e n o f e n k e l e m i n u t e n n a a r huis. g. * QP: Bill d r a n k m u c h too m u c h or a l i t t l e b i t fbiItfvhi'ih wine . if. W i m d r o n k v e e l te v e e l o f e e n b e e t j e t ü f é i t wijn. h. * J o h n b o u g h t a l i t t l e b i t m o r e o r a lot • * Jan kocht een beetje meer of een heleboel ih é if . It m a y be w o r t h w h i l e tail. The rule of to c o n s i d e r G a p p i n g N-Gapping differs d i s c u s s e d a b o v e in s e v e r a l re s p e c t s . to coordinations only similarly constrained: (see 2.1.5. in N P s from in s o m e the de V-Gapping First, V - G a p p i n g a p p l i e s above), N-Gapping is not ? - 28 • (55) a. A f t e r the dog w i t h a c o w ' s li v e r died, he w a n t e d to b uy one I I I w i t h f i v e legs, T o e n de h o n d m e t ee n k o e i e l e v e r g e s t o r v e n was, w i l d e hi j er e e n 1 1 I I m et v i j f p o t e n k o p e n . (When the dog w i t h a c o w ' s li v e r d i e d had, w a n t e d he th<=re one //// w i t h f i v e legs buy) b. A d og w i t h f i v e legs w i l l w i n f r o m one I I I with two tails. E e n h o n d m et v i j f p o t e n zal w i n n e n v a n e e n ///// me t twee s t a a rten. Observe that d og h o n d ■ In or absent N this need is n o t not be a case a linguistic present. V-Gapping c a n n o t do w i t h o u t a full (56) necessarily N-Gapping, of d e l e t i o n of antecedent on the of other the hand linguistic antecedent. ( D i s c u s s i n g d o gs:) My f a t h e r once b o u g h t one w i t h five legs. M i j n v a d e r k o c h t e r e e n s e en m e t v i j f poten. (5?) (J o h n s h o w s that he c a n p e e l a p p l e s : ) L o o k at m e ! "i st u m n K i j k eens! Second, 2 .1.1.). however, *Ik pears! A peren ! V - G a p p i n g d e l e t e s true v a r i a b l e s If N-Gapping deletes more (as s h o w n in s e c t i o n than a single N or N' , the o u t p u t is u n g r a m m a t i c a l : (58) a. *KP e t e r ' s s t o r y ab o u t the e x p l a n a t i o n o f these sentences, and Max's m n i A n u n u i m t u m u of these p h r a s e s . * E en v e r h a a l v a n P e t e r o v e r de v e r k l a r i n g v a n d e z e zinnen, en van deze zinsdelen. v a n Jan 1 ' - 29 - * b. R o m e ' s hope of the d e s t r u c t i o n of C a r t h a g e a n d Carthage's * of Rome. 14>t I P h i I De h o o p v a n R o m e op de v e r n i e t i g i n g v a n C a r t h a g o en /t^izS^izS v a n C a r t h a g o 4>i>/ van R o m e . * c. R o m e ' s attempt, to d e s t r o y C a r t h a g e a n d C a r t h a g e ' s Af-f-i'slit / t<t / * Rome. De p o g i n g v a n R o m e C a r t h a g o te v e r w o e s t e n en ? M / ] Z v a n (In Dutch, N-Gapping independent reasons; Carthago Rome t i / after a genitive therefore, . NP is examples impossible with an for agentive p o s t n o m i n a l PP are g i v e n . ) The u n g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of (58) sh o w s it to be u n l i k e l y that N - G a p p i n g can be f o r m u l a t e d as a rule of v a r i a b l e de l e t i o n . Fina l l y , N-Gapping se e m s to be m o s t a c c e p t a b l e in those c a s e s w h e r e the N d e l e t e d r e s e m b l e s V. Thus, compare (59) and (60) : (59) The doll w i t h b l u e eyes of J o h n ' s and w i t h c u r l i n g h a i r of P e t e r ' s , ... De p op m et b l a u w e o g e n v a n J a n en k r u l l e n v a n Peter, (60) met ... The r e v i e w of J o h n ' s b o o k b y Max, of J o h n ' s a r t i c l e b y Susan, and ... De k r i t i e k v a n M a x op Jans b o e k en ^ v a n H a r r y op Jans a r t i k e l , ... F u r t h e r s t u d y m i g h t r e v e a l that G a p p i n g of " n o m i n a l " n o u n s is d i f f e r e n t f r o m G a p p i n g of " v e r b a l " nou n s . Many uncertainties remain regarding the analysis of N-Gapping, b ut the a b o v e - m e n t i o n e d d i f f e r e n c e s b e t w e e n N - G a p - ping V-Gapping and collapsed into ping cour t ) tout one. suggest The applies that domains are VP, these rules cannot in w h i c h V - G a p p i n g S, and o b s e r v a t i o n in n e e d of an e x p l a n a t i o n . S' only. be (or G a p This is an ? - 30 - 2.1.6. T H E C O O R D I N A T E S T R U C T U R E C O N S T R A I N T A N D A C R O S S THE-BOARD APPLICATIONS The Coordinate prohibits movement contained in a conjunct. c a n n o t be moved, (63) Structure Constraint of a c o n j u n c t , Thus, (R o s s 1967, 89) a n d m o v e m e n t o f an e l e m e n t a p p l e s in b o t h (61) and (62) as s h o w n by (63) a n d (64) r e s p e c t i v e l y ; W h i c h a p p l e s d o e s J o h n eat a n d d r i n k m i l k ? W e l k e a p p e l s e e t J a n en d r i n k t m e l k ? (64) * W h i c h a p p l e s does J o h n eat a n d p e a r s ? * W e l k e a p p e l s eet J a n en p e r e n ? In o r d e r ment to c o v e r the rule, altered the slightly. rule Coordinate First of Gapp i n g , w h i c h Is n o t a Structure observe that Constraint Gapping move must sets be itself a p a r t f r o m o t h e r rules o f s e n t e n c e g r a m m a r in that it a p p l i e s to " c o j a c e n t " and the dination : structures deletee ar e in (Koster 1978b, different 216). conjuncts The a n t e c e d e n t of the coor r No other r ule of s e n t e n c e g r a m m a r relates the two p o s i t i o n s l i n k e d by the l o w e r arrow. One m i g h t c o n c l u d e that G a p p i n g in this From respect another Coordinate It violates point appears that of Coordinate view, that by Gapping Structure however, Structure Constraint c o n t a i n a p ar t ly, the Gapping remnants may the not obeys the just as m u c h as W H - m o v e m e n t . variables deleted o f the c o o r d i n a t e d s t r u c t u r e , the Constraint. be a may n ot or a l t e r n a t i v e conjunct or an element c o n t a i n e d in a con j u n c t : (66) J o h n e a t s p e a r s an d d r i n k s m i l k a n d P e t e r ii- t i apples ■ # J a n eet p e r e n en d r i n k t m e l k en P e t e r appels (67) * J o h n e a t s b a n a n a s a n d p e a r s a n d P e t e r J a n eet b a n a n e n en p e r e n en P e t e r i i t apples a p p e l s ¿pi i>4 f i t ' T h i s s u g g e s t s tha t two p a r t s o f the rule o f G a p p i n g s h o u l d be clearly distinguished: on e relating s e n t e n c e a n d the g a p p e d s e n t e n c e , the o t h e r p art obeys relating the the complete anteceding as i l l u s t r a t e d b y (65), and r e m n a n t s o f the rule. O n l y the l a t t e r the C o o r d i n a t e S t r u c t u r e C o n s t r a i n t , cf. (66) and (67). M o r e wil l be sai d a b o u t this d i s t i n c t i o n in c h a p t e r 2. Ross Coordinate (1967, board phenomena. out of 9) Structure a class of Constraint, the 'e x c e p t i o n s ' so-called to the across-the- It t urns out that a c o n s t i t u e n t m a y be m o v e d a conjunct other conjuncts mentions in c a s e p a r a l l e l c o n s t i t u e n t s m o v e as w ell. See (68) t ions i n v o l v e d in the m o v e m e n t ) : out of (the a r r o w s l i n k the p o s i 32 - (68) I t ' s p o t a t o e s t h a t J o h n l i k e s , a n d M a r y h a t e s ; (G r o s u 1972, 220) D a t is l e t s w a t K a r e l w e l : lust en M a r i e n i e t A _____________ I It is clear that the t h e - b o a r d fa shion: rule of G a p p i n g a p p l i e s lust. in an a c r o s s - it r e d u c e s a c o o r d i n a t i o n w i t h an i n f i n i t e n u m b e r o f c o n j u n c t s , u n d e r i d e n t i t y w i t h the f i r s t co n j u n c t : (69) a. J o h n eats apples, P e t e r banan a s , M a r y ié - ü a nd Bill ié - té grapes. J a n eet a p pels, banan e n , pears, Piet peren, ..., en W i m Marie druiven. b. J o h n likes p o t a t o e s a nd M a r y ItV - ié p o t a t o e s an d J o h n bea n s , or Mary beans. Jan h o u d t v a n a a r d a p p e l s en M a r i e J v a n bonen, o f M a r i e W v M # v a n b o n e n en J a n |10yl(dli v a n aardappels. The examples nation of (66), the the-board (67), Coordinate application well. of (69) indicate Structure rules is that Constraint relevant to the and combi across- Gapping as ' There plain are both the-board and and the two a t t e m p t s in the Coordinate application Williams (1978). of recent Structure syntactic Schachter literature Constraint rules: and Schachter rephrases the to e x across(1977) Coordinate S t r u c t u r e C o n s t r a i n t as a C o o r d i n a t e C o n s t i t u e n t C o n d i t i o n , a s u r f a c e s t r u c t u r e c o n s t r a i n t r e q u i r i n g that "the c o n s t i t u e n t s o f a c o o r d i n a t e s t r u c t u r e m u s t b e l o n g to the same syntactic category and have the same semantic f u n c t i o n ”. Thus, (70) function, is r u l e d o ut b y l a c k o f p a r a l l e l i s m o f s y n t a c t i c and (71) is r u l e d out f or s e m a n t i c r e a s o n s : r - 33 - (70) * It's o d d for J o h n to be b u s y a n d that H e l e n is idle now. * Ik w i s t n i e t of hij k w a m en dat zij w e g b l e e f . (I k n e w n ot w h e t h e r he c a m e a n d that she s t a y e d a w a y .) (71) J o h n ate w i t h hi^_ m o t h e r a n d w i t h g o o d a p p e t i t e . J a n at m e t z i j n m o e d e r en m e t v e e l s m a a k . Schächter claims that t h i s f o r m u l a t i o n c o v e r s Structure Constraint ceptions. The underlying rule application and thus obey untouched problem the is how with idea to the th a t by are Constituent syntactic Coordinate and ex across-the-board still parallel Condition. Left crucial notion of parallelism. define Schächter's the C o o r d i n a t e across-the-board conjuncts Coordinate is the is coordinate the however Therefore, together semantic Constituent The sameness. Condition can be s e e n as a r e s t a t e m e n t o f the p r o b l e m at best. Williams the-board torized rule (1978) gives a applications. simultaneously, as formalized Coordinate illustrated account of structures in (72), acrossare fac- a structure to w h i c h the rule of W H - m o v e m e n t is a p p l i c a b l e : (72) C O M P [John saw who] s [Bill hit wh o ] s 1 2 and 4 3 A p p l i c a t i o n o f W H - m o v e m e n t to this f a c t o r i z a t i o n y i e l d s (73), A c o p y of w h o is p l a c e d in C O M P a n d f a c t o r 3 is d e l e t e d : (73) C O M P [John sa w who [Bill hit Williams' proposal factor contained board implies * }s * Is that in a c o o r d i n a t e application, sin c e torized simultaneously. a nd the only structure coordinate way to change a is b y a c r o s s - t h e - structures m u s t be fac- r - 34 - Furthermore, the 32) Williams factorization 5 the . In effect, ol d result: of Coordinate must Structure separate condition (Williams on the n o t i o n Constraint of a c o n j u n c t apply a structures this constraint movement conjunct proposes coordinate across-the-board, 'factor' yield or an e l e m e n t t he contained or e l s e on 1978, and s ame in a the o u t p u t is ungrammatical. This nomena ingeneous in terms a dds to Ross' to r s count of account of the c o o r d i n a t e factorization of structural analysis a mechanism as "parallel". It structure phe descriptions that s p e c i f i e s w h i c h f a c predicts t hat object-who and m o r e e m b e d d e d s u b j e c t - w h o are p a r a l l e l in (74), w h i l e o b j e c t who and equally embedded subject-who in (75) are not paral lel: (74) a. I k n o w the m a n w h o J o h n l i k e s a n d we h o p e w i l l win. b. C O M P % (75) a. b. For some is not [John l i k e s who] s [we h o p e [who and will win]g]g I k n o w a m a n w h o Bil l s a w a n d l i k e s M ary. COMP f\ reason, [Bill s a w w h o ]s [who the reproducible difference in Dut c h , an d likes Mary]g illustrated neither in in (74) a n d (75) relative clauses, n o r in W H - q u e s t i o n s : ' (74') a. *Ik ken de m a n d i e h i j a a r d i g v i n d t e n w i j h o p e n da t zal w i n n e n . ■ (I k n o w the m a n w h o he l i k e s a n d w e h o p e t hat wi l l win) b. * W i e v i n d t hij a a r d i g e n h o p e n zij d a t zal winnen? (Who d o e s he l ike a n d h o p e t h e y t h a t w i l l w in?) F - 35 -}f (75') a. Ik k e n de m a n d i e hij a a r d i g v i n d t e n h a a r zag. (I k n o w the m a n w h o he l i k e s a n d h e r saw) # Wie v i n d t hij a a r d i g e n z a g h a a r ? (Who d o e s he like a n d saw he r ? ) Observe that surface filter the u n g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of prohibiting (74') e m p t y N Ps is n o t due to the a f t e r d a t , as s h o w n by (74"). (74") a. Ik ke n de m a n d i e wij h o p e n d a t zal w i n n e n . (I k n o w the m a n w h o we h o p e t h a t w i l l win) b. Wie h o p e n zij d a t zal w i n n e n ? (Who hope t h e y that will w i n ? ) ” See Mali-ng and' Z a e n e n (1978) a nd the r e f e r e n c e s c i t e d •there. The u n i v e r s a l i t y W i l l i a m s c l a i m s f or h i s d e f i n i t i o n of f a c t o r is thus c h a l l e n g e d . For u n c l e a r r e a s o n s D u t c h d i f f e r s in this r e s p e c t f r o m E ngli s h . O ne fin a l p r o b l e m for the n o t i o n o f s i m u l t a n e o u s f a c t o r i z a t i o n is w o r t h p o i n t i n g out. C o n s i d e r s e n t e n c e s such as in (76), s t r u c t u r e d as in (77). (76) a. J o h n gave the b o o k to M a r y a n d ) < / $ & / 4 the r e c o r d to Sue, or JóV ufi/ié-fi the b o o k to Sue and the r e c o r d to Mary. J a n g a f h e t b o e k a a n M a r y en f & i i / Sue, of de p l a a t a a n h e t b o e k a a n Sue en ï M / m de p l a a t a a n Mary. b. J o h n i n v i t e d Sue a n d M a x id Sue a n d J o h n % Ma r y , \ J o h n v r o e g S u s a n en M a x i t a t S u s a n en J o h n Marie. or M a x Mary. Marie, of Max f - In (76), an element of 36 - S4 , Sg , and Sg is deleted under i d e n t i t y w i t h an e l e m e n t of Sg. O b s e r v e t h a t t h i s d e l e t i o n is possible parts. only The if S 2 , S 4 , Sg, and Sg d e l e t i o n is not p o s s i b l e a n d S 4 are identical all contain identical in case o n l y p a r t s of to p a r t s of Sg a n d S g r e s p e c t i v e l y (see (78) ): (78) a. * J o h n gave the b o o k to M a r y a n d he h a n d e d the r e c o r d to Sue, or M U M the b o o k to Sue a n d the r e c o r d to Mary. * J o h n g a f h e t b o e k a a n M a r y en hij o v e r h a n d i g d e de p l a a t a a n Sue, of h e t b o e k a a n Sue en p l a a t a a n Mary. b. * J o h n s aw Sue a n d M a x i n v i t e d Mary, Sue a n d J o h n or M a x Mary. J a n z ag S u s a n en M a x v r o e g Mari e , of Max S u s a n en J a n i r f i i t Marie. In o r d e r to d e r i v e that and X 2 in (76) a nd e x c l u d e (79) are (78), W i l l i a m s s t i p u l a t e s identical, w h e r e a s X 1 a n d X~ in (80) are not: (79) X, [„ J o h n g a v e ... [q J o h n g a v e X, ... 6 L ' (80) X, „ J o h n gave 2 0 0 [„ J o h n g a v e X 2= 6 [Q he h a n d e d „ he h a n d e d 4 8 - 8 ... F - 37 - This implies prior that a d e f i n i t i o n o f i d e n t i t y n e e d s to r e f e r to application W il l i a m s ' relates account the the-board of Ga p p i n g , is interesting, Coordinate w h i c h is a p o t e n t i a l p r o b l e m . however, Structure r ul e a p p l i c a t i o n in that Constraint and in an e x p l i c i t way. it cor across- Further study m i g h t s olve the p r o b l e m s n o t i c e d above. 2.1.7. C O N C L U S I O N : T H E F O R M U L A T I O N OF G A P P I N G The p r e s e n t l y m o s t of Gapping was important characteristic pointed out r ule of s e n t e n c e gr a m m a r . has been 410) section o f the rule 2.1.4.: Gapping is a In the rec e n t l i t e r a t u r e t h i s p o i n t the s u b j e c t of s ome debate. H a n k a m e r a n d Sag (1976, suggest Sag’ s in that statement Gapping is (1976, 192) indeed apply a rul e to of t his discourse, effect although is w o r d e d m ore carefully: "Gapping ca n in discourse, at least some times . (3.1.7.) S p e a k e r A: J o r g e is p e e l i n g an apple. S p e a k e r B: A n d I van 0 a n o range. It's not like this. to be is at all clear, ho w e v e r , The d i s c o u r s e a p e c u l i a r cas e actually a in what (3.1.7.) to m a k e of e x a m p l e s s e e m s to s o m e p e o p l e of two p e o p l e c o l l a b o r a t i n g on w h a t single sent e n c e , in which case Gapping s h o u l d p e r h a p s be r e s t r i c t e d to si n g l e s e n t e n c e s . A l t e r n a tively, discourse one might grammar, argue bu t begin with conjunctions, like ( 3 . 1.7.) that that Gapping s in c e is Gapped a rule clauses of must it is o n l y in p e c u l i a r s i t u a t i o n s that G a p p i n g ca n a p p l y i n t e r s e n t e n t i a l l y ."6 It a p p e a r s to me t hat this p r o b l e m c o n c e r n i n g the st a t u s of the rule formulation of of Gapping the rule. is in fact closely In p a r t i c u l a r : it related has been to the agreed u n a n i m o u s l y that in the rul e of G a p p i n g b o t h the full a n d the ? - 38 - reduced conjunct s h o u l d be m e n t i o n e d . ive f o r m u l a t i o n o f the rule, In t his jand, or) A w2 B 1 2 3 4 5 6 W1 7 1 2 3 4 5 6 0 w ents, T h i s y i e l d s an e x t e n s as in (81); 1 formula, one W3 W is a true v a r i a b l e constituent, variables or zero), To m y k n o w l e d g e , peculiar rule r ules o f s e n t e n c e conjuncts there are B' 10 W3 11 8 0 10 0 2 (a s t r i n g of c o n s t i t u of a of fo r coordination. identity presumably sentence on the to Furthermore, grammar. There (81) is a are no other to the i n t e r i o r of the Observe that the antecedent s t r u c t u r a l c h a n g e s of the rule, and parallelism. related in S a g ' s (3.1.7) is a is n o o t h e r rule of s e n t e n c e grammar which apply string has no bearing except 9 (one c o n s t i t u e n t or zero). g r a m m a r w h i c h s p r e a d s a c r o s s s p eake r s . very W 8 and A a n d B are c o n s t i t u e n t To t h i s f o r m u l a t i o n the d i s c o u r s e problem. A1 semantics, But these n ot to two notions sy n t a x . Thus, t here s e e m s to be no s y n t a c t i c m o t i v a t i o n to m e n t i o n the full anteceding s e ntence. On tion of Gapping would (76) (some of them the c o n t r a r y , run i n t o repeated the extensive formula t r o u b l e w i t h e x a m p l e s such as here for convenience in (82)). O b s e r v e that the d o m a i n o f (81) c a n n e v e r be d e f i n e d so as to include (82) (82), bu t to e x c l u d e (83):7 J o h n i n v i t e d Sue a n d M a x M ary, or M a x Sue a n d J o h n f s j i i i t i f i Mary. J o h n v r o e g S u s a n en M a x S u s a n en J o h n Ma r i e , of M a x M arie. (83) * J o h n i n v i t e d Sue a n d M a x t ' é ' f i t i é M ary, t r f i i i t é i Sue a n d J o h n J o h n v r o e g S u s a n en M a x i r f é é i Ma r i e , ffié i or M a x i n v i t e d Mary. S u s a n en J o h n v r o e g M arie. of M a x F - 39 - For t hese r e a sons, the extensive formulation of Gapping must be r e j e c t e d an d we p o s t u l a t e a s m a l l - s c a l e f o r m u l a t i o n in i ts a place; (84) G a p p i n g W. 1 1 While A 5 adequacy at ==> will h ave l east grammar Fo r constituent, The is one 0 2 to be clear 0 4 0 demonstrated, point in its this favor a very Ways (the between 2 will observed 2.1,4. constituent (cf. that- f a c t o r s 1-5 De Haan are one as no s u r p r i s e h o w e v e r , and 3, be formulation the in rule 2.1.1. so (the of the as to remnants that r ule meet are are S', S an d VP) Furthermore, string discussed. in major will and be d i s c u s s e d chapter an d the It will of the (the rule o b e y s I s l a n d C o n s t r a i n t s ) domains wil l come constrain the a n t e c e d i n g (84) single implies unconstrained to constituents), chapters a this a d e s i r a b l e result. characteristics 2,1.5. form (84) observation a Ga p p i n g . by W„ V, ,O it t r i g g e r s the c o n v e n t i o n t hat the f a c t o r s o f a rule 74), (84) 4 has sentence 1977, 3 it s priori: B d 2 formulation of W0 2 the in relation deleted string omitted be claimed that this r e l a t i o n c a n n o t be p r o p e r l y c o n s i d e r e d in s e n t e n c e g r a m m a r . 2.2. B A C K W A R D C O N J U N C T I O N R E D U C T I O N It c a n be rule of juncts which the rul e are s h o w n in at Backward precede of G a p p i n g serious enough l e a s t five s e p a r a t e w a y s t h a t the Conjunction the final (a f o r w a r d to prohibit t hey ca n be l a i d ou t as f o l lows. Reduction (reduction conjunct) re d u c t i o n ) . a collapse is in con different from These differences of the pair, and E - 40 - 2.2.1. M A J O R C O N S T I T U E N C Y The g a p p i n g e x a m p l e s in the p a r a l l e l backward tical. indicates This (85) are u n g r a m m a t i c a l , w h e r e a s reduction examples that Gapping, in but (86) are g r a m m a not Backward Con j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n l e a v e s m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s b e h ind. (85) a. * J o h n is c o n f i d e n t of a s u c c e s s f u l o u t i n g a n d Peter H d e p e n d e n t on £ /& $ ¿ i é é é t ' k t / * J a n is vol h o o p op e e n g o e d e a f l o o p en P e t e r Ü b. a f h a n k e l i j k v a n é é iï/ É é é é é / é - t té<t>i> • J o h n c a m e up w i t h e v i d e n c e a g a i n s t t h a t p r o p o s a l an d M a x ÊéiAé / $ ■ $ a r g u m e n t s in s u p p o r t of Jan leverde bewij z e n tegen dat v o o rstel en Peter lé té M é (86) a. argumenten voor i.& .tlir M t& tit ■ J o h n is c o n f i d e n t of tiM t , M/ a n d P e t e r is d e p e n d e n t o n a s u c c e s s f u l o u t i n g at the track, (Ross 1967) J a n is vol h o o p op en P e t e r is a f h a n k e l i j k v a n e e n goe d e a f l o o p v a n de o n d e r n e m i n g , b. J o h n came up w i t h e v i d e n c e a g a i n s t a n d P e t e r a d d u c e d .arguments in s u p p o r t o f that proposal. Jan leverde bewijzen tegen en Peter v o e r d e a r g u m e n t e n a a n v o o r dat v o o r s t e l . It w as should shown be in major (41) above constituents. that (86) the remnants shows that of Gapping there such restriction on Backward Conjunction Reduction. is no - 41 - 2.2.2. The T HE T A R G E T OF B A C K W A R D C O N J U N C T I O N R E D U C T I O N English u s e d as a test tal (1974, rule of Backward Conjunction for constituency by Hankamer 125) a nd English the rule Consider (87) an d (88) Bresnan deletes (1974). one It single ( B r e s n a n 1974, Reduction (1971, 96), appears fi n a l is Pos that in constituent. 615): (87) He t r i e d to p e r s u a d e t h e m but he c o u l d n ' t c o n v i n c e t h e m that he w a s right. (88) a. * H e t r i e d to p e r s u a d e $$. 4$/t f t & , but t he c o u l d n ' t c o n v i n c e t h e m that he w a s right. b. * H e t r i e d to p e r s u a d e t ^ s h i I I P h & t l ' s h < i l ' b & & H i U , b ut he c o u l d n ' t c o n v i n c e the s t u d e n t s that he w a s right. F or t h i s r eason, B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n in E n g l i s h is c o n s i d e r e d as a R i g h t N o d e R a i s i n g b y the l i n g u i s t s m e n t i o n e d above. The effects p r e s e n t e d in (89) of this raising ( M a l i n g 1972, are schematically re 103): (89) The particular by the structural argument that change it of (89) m i g h t automatically be b a c k e d up accounts for the i n t o n a t i o n a l b r e a k b e f o r e the r a i s e d node. The fact that B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n is a r u l e w h i c h d e l e t e s (or moves) Backward Conjunction variables) In analyzed and Gapping (which deletes c a n n o t be c o l l a p s e d to one r u l e in E n g l i s h . Dutc h , as Reduction in E n g l i s h a c o n s t i t u e n t i m p l i e s that Backward Conjunction a m o v e m e n t rule, m a y be dele t e d . Reduction cannot be si n c e m o r e t h a n o n e c o n s t i t u e n t C o n s i d e r the e x a m p l e s in (90), in w h i c h (res - 42 - pectively) PP plus S', NP plus V plus adverbial S', a n d NP p l u s PP are deleted: (90) a. Hij h e e f t n i e t o p e n l i j k v e r t e l d m a a r hij h e e f t wel d u i d e l i j k g e m a a k t a a n h e n da t hij origelijk had, (He h a s n o t pufcilicly tol d ti> / itt é ti/ iÏÏè - t/%<£ but he h a s (adv.) c l e a r m a d e to t h e m that he w r o n g h a d - b e e n ) b. He t is de g e w o o n t e dat ik v o o r h e m tééifitiiï/i'éé f/'fié /Ü éé ïrtrté iï en hij v o o r mij de k a a r t e n s c h u d t v o o r we b e g i n n e n . (It is the c u s t o m that I for h i m a n d he f o r me the c a r d s s h u f f l e s u n u iM / m m b e f o r e we start) c. Je k u n t e e n b e r o e p d o e n op u a n m u t u m i H H - / &i i / 9 M M of g e b r u i k m a k e n v a n di e i n f o r m a t i e bij h e t b e a n t w o o r d e n v a n die M t !M vraag. (You ca n a n a p p e a l m a k e to f V k i f / X t t ^ f ^ t i - 4 ^ / W o r u s e m a k e of that i n f o r m a t i o n in a n s w e r i n g that q u e s t i o n ) For this cannot remains reason, be to languages the considered be are deletion a explained, different process Right of on Node course, this illustrated in Raising in why the rules since in point, (90) D utch. in all It both other r e s p e c t s t h e y are v e r y s i m ilar. 2.2.3. O N E T A R G E T D E L E T I O N Gapping tences (cf. deletes discontiguous parts of c o o r d i n a t e d (91)). Reduction Backward Conjunction sen is d i f f e r ent f r o m G a p p i n g in that it does no t d e l e t e d i s c o n t i g u o u s l y : - 43 - (91) a. A r izona elected Goldwater Senator, Pennsylvania and Schweiker ( J a c k e n d o f f 1971, ~ 24) A r i z o n a k o o s G o l d w a t e r tot p r e s i d e n t en Pennsylvania t ié é b. Sch w e i k e r U t H H i i U U . M a x w r i t e s p&.et ry in the b a t h r o o m a n d S c h w a r z r a d i c a l p a m p h l e t s jiyi/ M a x s c h r i j f t p o e z i e in de b a d k a m e r e n S c h w a r z é itifïiît c. p a m f l e t t e n iii/ 4 i/ Î> & ( z W s W . J a c k b e g g e d E l s i e to g e t m a r r i e d a n d W i l f r e d Phoebe M U M J an v r o e g E l s i e m e t h e m te t r o u w e n e n W i l f r e d if M i Phoebe (92) a, ^ A r i z o n a 4 t 4 4 t é $ G o l d w a t e r $44-&t<tt, a n d Pennsylvania elected Schweiker Senator. ^Arizona G o l d w a t e r t<t>t j H i i i M t t en ’ P e n n s y l v a n i a k o o s S c h w e i k e r tot p r e s i d e n t . b. * M a x i t f f i é é p o e t r y i r h I t t y i and Schwarz w r i t e s r a d i c a l p a m p h l e t s in the b a t h r o o m . Max u u t m poezie en Schwarz s c h r í j f t p a m f l e t t e n in de b a d k a m e r . c. * J a c k E l s i e t4 ! A i t ! th ê .ttt4 4 a n d W i l f r e d b e g g e d P h o e b e to get m a r r i e d . J a n f t 4 4 i E l s i e tfr4t/iTMort/t i / en Wilfred v r o e g P h o e b e m e t h e m te t r o uwen. 2.2.4. ISLAND SENSITIVITY Unlike Gappi n g , island-sensitive. ture C o n s t r a i n t Backward It p r e s u m a b l y in E n g l i s h Conjunction obeys the Reduction Coordinate is not Struc (see t he u n g r a m m a t i c a l e x a m p l e in (93a)), b u t it v i o l a t e s the S e n t e n t i a l S u b j e c t a n d C o m p l e x NP Constraints : - 44 - (93) a. Coordinate Structure Constraint: * A l f o n s e c o o k e d the b e a n s and Harry c o o k e d the p o t a t o e s an d the rice. A l f o n s k o o k t e b o n e n é ji/ t i i i t en Harrie kookte a a r d a p p e l s e n rijst. b. Sentential Sübgect C o n s t r a i n t : That A l f o n s e c o o k e d t t y é / t ï i i a n d t h a t H a r r y ate the rice is f a n t a s t i c . Dat A l f o n s de r i j s t ¡zSjié .t en dat H a r r y de a a r d a p p e l s o p a t is f a n t a s t i s c h . c. C o m p l e x NP C o n s t r a i n t : A l f o n s e d i s c u s s e d the q u e s t i o n o f w h i c h rice i i a n d M a r y d i s c u s s e d the q u e s t i o n é o f w h i c h b e a n s we w o u l d eat. A l f o n s b e s p r a k de v r a a g w e l k e rijst •if-it en H a r r y b e s p r a k de v r a a g w e l k e b o n e n we z o u d e n eten. Th e s e c o m p a r a t i v e l y u n r e s t r i c t e d a p p l i c a t i o n a l p o s s i b i l ities allowed other embeddings to Backward Conjunction as First we l l . Reduction observe a p p l i e s to t o p m o s t c o o r d i n a t e d s e n t e n c e s . in S 2 under identity with S ^ , b ut not w i t h Sg in a s t r u c t u r e s u c h as (94): The f o l l o w i n g e x a m p l e s i l l u s t r a t e this: that surface Gapping in only G a p p i n g is p o s s i b l e in under identity - 45 - (95) S u s a n s a i d that h e r b r o t h e r w a s ill a n d M a r y that h e r s i s t e r w a s ill. ié - i i S u s a n zei dat h a a r b r o e r t j e z i e k w a s en M a r i e dat h a a r z u sje z i e k was. té i (96) S u s a n s a i d that h e r b r o t h e r w a s ill a n d M a r y s a i d that h e r s i s t e r i i & i / i t t ■ S u s a n zei d a t h a a r b r o e r t j e z i e k w a s en M a r i e zei dat h a a r zus j e Backward Conjunction . Reduction on the other hand deletes e l e m e n t s w h i c h are c o n j u n c t - f i n a l , w h e t h e r e m b e d d e d or not: (97) Susan that h e r b r o t h e r w a s ' i l l a n d M a r y s a i d tha t h e r s i s t e r was ill. * Susan H f dat h a a r b r o e r t j e z i e k w a s en M a r i e zei dat h a a r z u sje z i e k was. (98) S u s a n s a i d that h e r b r o t h e r i t é , é / t ït a n d M a r y sai d tha t h e r s i s t e r w a s ill. S u s a n zei dat h a a r b r o e r t j e en M a r i e zei dat h a a r z u sje z i e k was. In this leled by s u c h as respect, any "late Backward ru l e of stylistic Conjunction sentence R e d u c t i o n is u n p a r a l grammar. Only housekeeping rule" a description s e e m s to a p p r o a c h its c h a r a c t e r i s t i c s . 2.2.5. T H E D O M A I N S OF B A C K W A R D C O N J U N C T I O N R E D U C T I O N Backward Conjunction Reduction a p p l i c a t i o n to a s p e c i f i c d o main: of all s o r t s o f c o n s t i t u e n t s . is not restricted in it a p p l i e s to c o o r d i n a t i o n s 46 - (99) VP: a. I a m c o n f i d e n t of an d d e p e n d e n t on a s u c c e s s f u l o u t i n g at the track, Ik v e r t r o u w op en b e n a f h a n k e l i j k v a n een g o e d e a f l o o p v a n de onderneming. . NP: b. J o h n i n t e r v i e w e d p e o p l e w h o like an d p e o p l e w h o d i s l i k e p o t a t o e s . Ja n o n d e r v r o e g m e n s e n di e wel f.é 'ié é é en m e n s e n di e n i e t v a n a a r d a p p e l s PP: h ouden. - c. J o h n w a s s t a n d i n g o n a n e w tab l e . - ■ . o r on an old ■ J a n s t o n d op e e n n i e u w U t é ï t ê i o f op e e n o u d taf e l t j e . . d. J o h n j u m p e d o v e r t h r e e ¿ é t é t o r o v e r f o u r g a t e s . Ja n s p r o n g o v e r d rie yi4)£iéé o f o v e r v i e r he k j e s . Furthermore, there are no r e s t r i c t i o n s o n the c a t e g o r y o f the d e l e t e d el e m e n t : and examples throughout thi s in (99) N or N P is d e l e t e d , of deletion section. of other in (98) V P s are, categories a re given F r o m t h i s a n d the o t h e r d i f f e r e n c e s between Gapping and Backward Conjunction Reduction enumerated above it Backward follows that the two Conjunction' Reduction rules is an cannot be collapsed. e x t r e m e l y a w k w a r d rule in that it v i o l a t e s n e a r l y e v e r y v i a b l e s y n t a c t i c c o n s t r a i n t . In the absence of a sufficiently developed theory of t hese p h e n o m e n a we w i l l leave the r ule at t his u n d e v e l o p e d stage. - 47 3. L I M I T A T I O N S IN D E S C R I P T I V E D E V I C E S Having shown and Backward the independence Conjunction of Reduction, the rules we will of Gapping in t h i s s e c t i o n s u b s t a n t i a t e the c l a i m m a d e in the i n t r o d u c t i o n to this c h a p ter, in that a these rules description compare the of are the Sentence Conjunction Conjunction Hypothesis, junction to be p r e f e r r e d . rules is of Forward only transformations coordination phenomena. Hypothesis and will conclude S econd, Conjunction D e l e t i o n a nd C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t required Fir s t , we will and the P h r a s a l that p h r a s a l we w i l l Reduction, argue Left con that the Peripheral are u n n e c e s s a r y o r i n a d e q u a t e d e s c r i p t i o n s of the c o o r d i n a t i o n p h e n o m e n a . ' 3.1. P H R A S A L C O N J U N C T I O N vs. R E S T R U C T U R I N G / R E L A B E L I N G Generative grammar has its d e s c r i p t i v e devi c e s . cal rules; redundancy overlap with a l w a y s k n o w n a c e r t a i n w e a l t h in Transformations structure rewriting rules; exist next preserving rule to l e x i transformations ordering overlaps with o u t p u t f i l t e r s a nd b o t h o b l i g a t o r y t r a n s f o r m a t i o n s a n d i n t e r preting rules available the have are filtering distinguished distinctions dancy a rules), a ef f e c t . priori transformations is always it of gross coverage (cf. between not clear o f f e r a s i g n i f i c a n t p r e d i c t i o n in state Though affairs of gives data a as Wasow and that devices (1977) lexical the is edge of to distinctions the w a r n i n g very for redun the case u n d e r stu d y . specific such the little This that i n t erest, si n ce the l a t t e r is l i k e l y to i l l u s t r a t e m e r e l y t h a t the rule system makes only few a priori claims about the d a t a a n d is v a g u e e n o u g h to e n u m e r a t e the d a t a in s o m e f a s hion. In the g r a m m a r of c o o r d i n a t i o n we the fi r s t face t h i s p r o b l e m for time as the c h o i c e b e t w e e n the P h r a s a l C o n j u n c t i o n H y p o t h e s i s a nd the S e n t e n c e C o n j u n c t i o n H y p o t h e s i s 1970-1971). latter An underlying hypothesis (Tai (Dougherty a s s u m p t i o n o f the d e f e n d e r s o f the 1969; Hankamer 1971; Stockwell, 48 - Schachter rules and cannot conjunction reduction manner Partee be to junctions restricted may phrasal at is, that with coordination if o ne be g e n e r a t e d in the base, rules tha t 1973) dispensed no in be extra suc h formulated conjunctions a costs. w'ay in The that base only and thus such derive an from rules t he reduction assumes phrasal that such unrestricted sentence con may then be S-label will be a l l o w e d to g e n e r a t e c o n j u n c t i o n s . A s e r i o u s d r a w b a c k o f the S e n t e n c e sis is, however, that transformations Conjunction Hypothe need to be equipped i n e v i t a b l y w i t h the p o w e r of r e s t r u c t u r i n g a n d r e l a b e l i n g , order to (101) (Tai 1969, derive NP the for instance f r o m i ts u n d e r l y i n g f o r m 43): NP James The (100) John c ame d e f e n d e r s o f the Phra:sal C o n j u n c t i o n H y p o t h e s i s , other hand, a rgue t hat p h r a s a l deep s t r u c t u r e anyway, e.g. (102) a. conjunction on is n e e d e d in in v i e w of s e n t e n c e s s u c h as: John forms a curious pair and Mary forms a c u r i o u s pair, Ja n v o r m t e e n b i j z o n d e r p a a r en M a r i e v o r m t e e n b i j z o n d e r paar. b. in J o h n an d M a r y f o r m a c u r i o u s pair. Ja n en M a r i e v o r m e n een b i j z o n d e r paar. _ 49 - U n d e r the are assumption that phrasal coordination constructions generated (Dougherty 1968) di r e c t l y , 1 9 7 0-1971, Blom transformational Phrasal Conjunction structuring ruled out and a they propose 1975) relabeling in of any strongly limit completely abolish (Dik reduction rules. The coordination Hypothesis priori or to suggests at coordinate generative least that structures grammar can of a re be human language. If we we will and assume do here, Gapping are phrasal c o n j u n c t i o n f o r all categories as the r u l e s of B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n necessary, as argued above, for sentences su ch as: (103) J o h n a te a n d P e t e r d r a n k a lot. J a n at en P e t e r d r o n k v e e l . (104) J o h n d r a n k w h i s k y a n d P e t e r gin. Jan dronk whisky en Peter O n the o t h e r hand, gin. if we a s s u m e the r u l e s o f B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n a n d Gappi n g , p h r a s a l c o n j u n c t i o n is n e c e s s a r y as well parallel for sentences such as (105) and (107), since the Backward Conjunction Reduction and Gapping examples are u n g r a m m a t i c a l (105) (cf. (106) a nd (108)). H e tri e d to p e r s u a d e a n d c o n v i n c e t h e m t h a t he w a s right. (106) H e t r i e d to p e r s u a d e , and he t r i e d to c o n v i n c e t h e m that he w a s right. (107) J o h n ate f r e s h m e a t a n d v e g e t a b l e s . J a n at v e r s e v l e e s w a r e n en g r o e n t e s . (108) * J o h n ate f r e s h m e a t a n d P e t e r < ft v e g e t a b l e s . J a n at v e r s e v l e e s w a r e n en P e t e r In one hand some and inst a n c e s , however, phrasal Backward Conjunction groentes. c o n j u n c t i o n o n the Reduction and Gapping on - 50 the o t h e r ove r l a p . Consider (109): (109) J o h n sent a b u n c h of f l o w e r s a nd a pie to Mary. J a n z o n d een bos b l o e m e n en e en taa r t a a n Marie. This sentence in the base, derives either from phrasal c o n j u n c t i o n of N Ps or f r o m a ‘ '“ c o n j u n c t i o n o f V P s (or Ss) by G a p p i n g and B ackward Conjunction Reduction: (110) J o h n sent a b u n c h of f l o w e r s and i O i f a pie to Mary. J a n z o n d een bos b l o e m e n en e e n t a art a a n Marie. T h i s o v e r l a p mu s t be c o n s i d e r e d as a w e a k n e s s in the p r e s e n t theory. In the r e m a i n d e r iate our claim ti o n are the show that junction fluous that of t h i s secti o n , o n l y two c o o r d i n a t i o n coordination Reduction in o r d e r to s u b s t a n t Gapping and Backward Conjunction Reduc and reduction Left in an a d e q u a t e a c c o u n t r e d u c t i o n rules, rules Peripheral suc h we will as F o r w a r d C o n Deletion are super of c o o r d i n a t i o n r e d u c t i o n p h e nomena. 3.2. F O R W A R D C O N J U N C T I O N . R E D U C T I O N Forward Conjunction Reduction is formulated as the m i r r o r image of B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n by R o s s (1967, 220). B o t h r u les are c o l l a p s e d into one C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n rule as in (1 1 1 ) : - 51 - Conjunction Reduction (111) a. [X [and - b. - A] H"] 1 2 3 [1 2 0] B # [and 1 2# - s -x] B 2 3 Condition; n B ==> (OPT) 3] 0 1 (OPT) A \ B B all o c c u r r e n c e s o f A are i d e n t i c a l . R o s s adds the f o l l o w i n g e x p l a n a t i o n : "T h i s notation coordinate number should node of be the interpreted category of c o n j u n c t s w h i c h e a c h of w h i c h e i t h e r ends c a t e g o r y A, w h e r e all of th e s e occurrences B, are a l s o to m e a n which that in any dominates any of the c a t e g o r y B, a n d or b e g i n s w i t h a c o n s t i t u e n t of o c c u r r e n c e s o f A are i d e n t i c a l , o f A are s u p e r i m p o s e d , all and adjoined to the c o n j o i n e d n o d e B." For Backward Conjunction i l l u s t r a t e d b y (89) Reduction, the e f f e c t s o f t h i s are ( r e p e a t e d h e r e for c o n v e n i e n c e ) . ( 112) In c o n t r a s t w i t h B a c k w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n , Conjunction Reduction cannot be shown to Forward introduce coor d i n a t i o n s of s t r i n g s that are not one c o n s t i t u e n t . In fact, constrained generated in by coordinations strings phrase of Ross' such Forward a way phrase of structure constituents, constituents). structure Conjunction that rule c f . (113) a n d (113 ' ) : i ts rules but Examples schema turn Reduction product (which not which out might to may must produce coordinations do be not be have been fit of the ungrammatical, - 52 - (113) a. The U n i v e r s i t y ' s s t u d e n t s are i n t e l l i g e n t a n d f é/ét'A'Ai'sM é freedom. (are) c o m m i t t e d to (Ross 1967) De u n i v e r s i t a i r e s t u d e n t e n z i j n i n t e l l i g e n t en (zijn) g e h e c h t a a n hun vrijheid. ^ b. He s e l l s b o o k s about f l o w e r s and poetry. Hij v e r k o o p t b o e k e n o v e r b l o e m e n en o v e r poezie. c. He se l l s old b o o k s and tfié / clothes. Hij v e r k o o p t oude b o e k e n en %f. ¿ ¡ / / étié-é kleren. d. The old c a r s a nd / </>t\i b i k e s of P e t e r all are f or sale. De oude a u t o ' s en é é / i w i f i e t s e n v a n P e t e r zijn a l l e m a a l te koop. . . * (113') a. The U n i v e r s i t y ' s s t u d e n t s are i n t e l l i g e n t a n d /y s r f i f f f faculty * freedom. De u n i v e r s i t a i r e s t u d e n t e n z i j n i n t e l l i g e n t en $ b. * is c o m m i t t e d to . 4 f a c u l t e i t is g e h e c h t aan z i j n v r i j h e i d . B o o k s about f l o w e r s are w o n d e r f u l a n d p o e t r y are dull. * B o e k e n o v e r b l o e m e n z i j n p r a c h t i g en p o e z i e z i j n saai. c. * O l d b o o k s are for s a l e in A m s t e r d a m a n d f>l$ c l o t h e s are f or s a l e in The Hague. * Oude b o e k e n z i j n te k o o p in A m s t e r d a m en k l e r e n z i j n te koop in D e n Haag. 53 - d. The old c a r s o f P e t e r a n d %$<£/<(>%$, b i k e s o f J o a n all are f o r sale. De oude a u t o ' s v a n P i e t e n $ van Jannie zijn allemaal It follows that the rul^e cannot be 4 / fietsen' te koop. shown to be necessary, s in c e c o o r d i n a t i o n s of c o n s t i t u e n t s c a n be g e n e r a t e d by p h r a se structure rules di r e c t l y , i.e. its structure preserving p r o p e r t y s u g g e s t s that F o r w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n d o e s not e x i s t at a l l . S e n t e n c e s w i t h i nitial c o o r d i n a t i o n s f o r m the s e c o n d set of o b s e r v a t i o n s by w h i c h F o r w a r d C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n b e c o m es implausible. initial to exclude conjunct are them. is deleted t his The rule coordinations, In indexed by deletion thus these by Forward is turns and o ut to .be s h o u l d be structures, a coordinator. inapplicable complicated the in in i t i a l of When frontal Conjunction Reduction, visible start to so as each elements the e f f e c t coordination, and of the r e s u l t is an u n g r a m m a t i c a l s e n t ence. T h i s c o m p l i c a t i o n is in fact n e c e s s a r y u n d e r b o t h v a r i a nts of rule c an Forward be Conjunction analyzed Reduction either as a imaginable. (such as in R o s s ’ f o r m u l a t i o n c i t e d a b o v e ) , in place. (114) assumptions: are a nd (115) in both or as a r e d u c t i o n coordination, cases, in in i t i a l the o u t p u t strings coordination, are n o t : (114) the rule s h o w the e f f e c t of t h e s e d i f f e r e n t in n o n - i n i t i a l identical Thus, raising-and-deletion non-initial coordination local filters or local rules lokale filters of lokale regels they - 54 i r e d u c t i o n in p l a c e =^> NP AP N local filters or l o kale filters of rules regels :raising a n d d e l e t i o n = ^ > AP NP, AP local t i i é t N C ^ AP NI\ N f i l t e r s or t é i é l r u l e s l o k a l e té ^ é - ïé f i l t e r s o f t é ^ k é li r e g e l s (115) initial coordination e i t h e r local of f i l t e r s or lokale filters of local rules lokale regels :r e d u c t i o n in p l a c e e i t h e r local f i l t e r s or t ü à ï of lokale filters of rules regels :rai s i n g a n d d e l e t i o n = = > local e i t h e r U i A t f i l t e r s or ï é i & t lokale f i l t e r s o f î é '¿ '¿ t é r e g e l s of rules - 55 - In i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n , Reduction quire result in additional both variants of Forward Conjunction ungrammatical explanation in outputs. a These grammar facts with re Forward C o n j u n c t i o n R e d u c t i o n , b u t f o l l o w f r o m a g r a m m a r w i t h o u t it. Th e r e junction which is one p r o b l e m for a t h e o r y w i t h o u t Reduction, deserves and with mentioning-: ( D o u g h e r t y 1970, conjunction coordination VP a nd a d e r i v e d s t r u c t u r e VP (116) phrasal 853). Forward Con of a deep i n s tead, structure a p p e a r s to be g r a m m a t i c a l , cf. S u c h s e n t e n c e s c a n be d e r i v e d by Forward Conjunction Reduction, b ut not by p h r a s a l c o n j u n c t i o n in the base. (116) a. J o h n w as h u n t i n g li o n s and w a s f r i g h t e n e d by snakes. ' Ja n m a a k t e jacht op l e e u w e n en w e r d b a n g g e m a a k t d o o r slangen. b. M a r y w as n e i t h e r a n x i o u s to p l e a s e n o r fun to squeeze. Marie was en niet geneigd om aardig te zijn en n i e t leuk o m mee te praten. (Mary w a s b o t h not i n c l i n e d f o r k i n d to be a n d n o t f un for w i t h to talk) c. F e w w r i t e r s are b o t h e x p l i c i t a n d e a s y to read. M a a r w e i n i g s c h r i j v e r s z i j n zowel e x p l i c i e t als g e m a k k e l i j k om te lezen. d. C u r v a l n e i t h e r h it J u l i e n o r w a s p u n c h e d by Ad o n i s . ..., dat C u r v a l n o c h J u l i a g e s l a g e n heeft, noch d oor A d o n i s g e d u w d werd. T he s e e x a m p l e s a p p e a r to c o n s t i t u t e a n i n s u r m o u n t a b l e p r o b l e m for a theory VPs in (116) Passive and Dougherty which without does n ot base-generate It-replacement. Ways-out (1970) and V e r g n a u d a p r i n c i p l e d account. directly all the the a p p l i c a t i o n o f t r a n s f o r m a t i o n s like (1974), have been sketched by b u t b o t h f a i l to offer - 56 - Dougherty (1970, 865) a s s u m e s that the d e e p s t r u c t u r e of s e n t e n c e s suc h as (116) l o o k s like (117): (117) hit J u l i e Passive applies to S^, w h i c h results Substitution Transformation yields in (118). Thereafter a (119): (118) NP Curvai was p u n c h e d by A d o n i s hit J u l i e A l t h o u g h o b s c u r e d by s e v e r a l a delta-VP analyses was punched by Adonis tricks, in d e e p .s t r u c t u r e , this which make u se of s u c h as the a d d i t i o n of a n a l y s i s is e q u i v a l e n t to relabeling and restructuring rules. Vergnaud (1974, 51) accounts for (116) rule of S u b j e c t D e l e t i o n or I n t e r p r e t a t i o n . t his rule h as no implications beyond by p o s t u l a t i n g a To m y k n o w l e d g e , (116) and therefore s h o u l d be c o n s i d e r e d as an ad h o c s o l u t i o n to the p r o b l e m . A n a d d i t i o n a l d i f f i c u l t y for b o t h D o u g h e r t y a n d V e r g n a u d - 57 - is that along are in some with to be instances the subject. expected V P s in (116), 3.3. of (116) auxiliaries Therefore, from more are promising deleted solutions t h e o r i e s w h i c h b a s e - g e n e r a t e all the cf. K o s t e r ( 1 9 7 8 b ) . ^ LEFT PERIPHERAL ‘ DELETION Consider (120): (120) J o h n gave a b o o k to M a r y a n d a b u n c h of f l o w e r s to Sue. Since this rules directly do n ot that sentence form it is cannot be g e n e r a t e d by p h r a s e structure (a b o o k to M a r y a n d a b u n c h of f l o w e r s to Sue one constituent) derived from a it seems fuller reasonable underlying to form assume such as (121) b y G a p p i n g : (121) J o h n gave a b o o k to M a r y a n d a bunch o f f l o w e r s to Sue. This assumption, (1976, s u ch however, 20 3 - 2 0 9 ) . as Sag (121): Left d o e s n ot p r e s e n t closely factorization, constructions a Peripheral Forward rejected specific Deletion. Conjunction constituents introduction factorization explicitly rule time, Sag cases Unfortunately, of to the his n ew a conjunct rule, Sag of Gapping. c an be prevented as (121). The fixing up an existing he Due to with complex this from with deletes Along a more two-step rule it only. gives rule Gapping such of Reduction: new generating procedure i n t r o d u c i n g a n e w rule (Left P e r i p h e r a l D e l e t i o n ) s a me by for a f o r m u l a t i o n o f the rule, w h i c h p r e s u m a b l y resembles leftperipheral the is introduces and, a more of at the complex f a c t o r i z a t i o n is c l e a r l y s u s p i c i o u s . Sag such as presents five (121) means by arguments of f or Gapping. not deriving The conclusion sentences of our r e v i e w will be that S a g ' s a r g u m e n t s are t o o m a r g i n a l to y i e l d - 58 - sufficient support for Left Peripheral Deletion as a rule d i f f e r e n t f r o m Gapping, S a g ' s first a r g u m e n t c o n c e r n s the p h e n o m e n o n o f p r e p o s i t i o n d e l e t i o n . He o f f e r s the following examples, in o r d e r to s h o w that L e f t P e r i p h e r a l D e l e t i o n d e l e t e s v e r b p l u s p r e p o s i tion, b ut G a p p i n g d o e s not: *>, (122) a. M y m o t h e r m e t w i t h the p r i n c i p a l o n T h u r s d a y and the d e a n o n F r i d a y ifif / M f W t / M i / is i M (Sag's ( 3 . 2 . 7 . a) ) b. M y s i s t e r sp o k e to Mrs. W i m b l e on F r i d a y a n d irii / sii i 14 1 / i i><t>11 / 1 & the d e a n o n S a t u r d a y (Sag's (3.2.7.b ) ) (123) a. * J o h n s p o k e to H a rry, a n d Bill Mike. (S a g 's ( 3 . 2 . 5 . a ) ) b. * J o h n w a s h a p p y w i t h h is g i r l f r i e n d , her boyfriend Crucially, and Betsy (Sag ' s ( 3 . 2 . 5 . b ) ) if the p r e p o s i t i o n in (122) is d e l e t e d b y Gapping, it is n ot c l e a r w h y G a p p i n g m a y n o t d e l e t e the p r e p o s i t i o n in (123). Therefore, Sag assumes that (122) is d e r i v e d b y Left Peripheral Deletion. At ment are first blush towards n ot the this generated by stylistically suggested by see M i l s a r k the (1974, It the constructions should (quite u n l i k e ma r k e d . colons a reasonably structured argu that Gapp i n g . t h a t th e s e c o n s t r u c t i o n s t ime se e m s conclusion in They (124) added, (122) however, (121)) are at the same permit (for be in a other list list reading phenomena 209)): (124) a. My m o t h e r m e t with: the p r i n c i p a l o n T h u r s d a y , a n d the d e a n o n Friday. b. My s i s t e r s p o k e to: Mrs. W i m b l e on F r i d a y , and the d e a n o n S a t u r d a y . c . ' J o h n w a s h a p p y with: h i s b o y f r i e n d o n Friday, an d hi s g i r l f r i e n d o n Sa t u r d a y . as - 59 - Thus, it is not c l e a r w h e t h e r s u c h p h e n o m e n a fall w i t h i n the p r o p e r d o m a i n o f gramm a r . licence" granted be as used to T h e y m a y b e l o n g to the " p o etic a d m e n a n d as arguments in (which not n e c e s s a r i l y su c h support receives s h o u l d p r e f e r a b l y not of the a list claim reading) that (121) c a n n o t be an i n s t a n c e of Gapping. The second (m a a r in Du t c h ) . argument’ ’ -centers Compare (125) % * S a n d y ate the b agels, creamcheese. around the c o o r d i n a t o r but (125) a nd (126). but Betsy the (Sag's (3.2.8 . ) ) % S a n d y at de koek j e s , m a a r B e t s y $.t de s m e e r k a a s . (126) B e t s y gave the b a g e l s to T o m m y , -but c r e a m c h e e s e to Mike. (Sag's the ( 3 . 2 . 9 . a)) B e t s y g af de k o e k j e s a an To m m i e , m a a r de s m e e r k a a s aan Mike. D e l e t i o n of a l e f t p e r i p h e r a l c o n s t i t u e n t (126), b ut (125). These ripheral deletion underlying the (contrast an d o e s not. form of examples seems are constituent illustrate to c o o r d i n a t i o n s Observe, (125) to be internal purportedly Deletion applies while Gapping when of examples is g r a m m a t i c a l , is however, awkward selected important as slightly cf. is not, cf. that Left Pe conjoined by b u t , that the u n r e d u c e d well. Furthermore, more felicitously f or a c o n j u n c t i o n w i t h but), the i n t e r n a l G a p p i n g is g r a m m a t i c a l : (127) a. Some p e o p l e like b agels, but others X SW creamcheese. S o m m i g e n h o u d e n v a n k o e k j e s , m a a r a n d e r e n ft(zSy van s m e e r k a a s . b. Some p e o p l e go by car, but o t h e r s ¿(zS by bike. S o m m i g e n g a a n m et de auto, m a a r a n d e r e n de fiets. met - 60 - T h i s i m p l i e s that a p r o p e r d e s c r i p t i o n of the peculiarities of b u t is n o t i l l u m i n a t e d b y a d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n L e f t P e r i p h e ral D e l e t i o n a n d Gapping. As a third argument, Sag a d d u c e s the f o l l o w i n g u n g r a m m a t i c a l i n s t a n c e s of G a p ping. ■ if . T h a t A l a n w a s l ate a n n o y e d B etsy, (128) a. and that S a n d y w a s lat e B ernie. * Fo r us to a p p o i n t A l a n w o u l d i n f u r i a t e B etsy, b. and for us to a p p o i n t S a n d y Bernie. He c l a i m s t h a t "t h e s e has ' (p. 206) examples escaped . illustrate notice in a the constraint literature, on Gapping namely: that "Gapping cannot apply after a sentential subject."" S a g p r e s e n t s n o m o t i v a t i o n fo r t his r u l e - s p e c i f i c c o n d i t i o n , and it seems difficult f e a t u r e s of G a p p i n g . To i l l u s t r a t e are different which relate it to any of the other t hat G a p p i n g a n d L e f t P e r i p h e r a l D e l e t i o n rules, peripheral to 10 Sa g the n c o m p a r e s deletion ha s applied (128) with before a (129), in sentential object. (129) a. I p r o v e d that the s k y is b l u e last T u e s d a y , and 1 that the e a r t h is r o u n d l a s t W e d n e s d a y . b. I p r e f e r for y o u to get the job w h e n I'm drunk, and f o r B e t s y to get the job w h e n I'm sober. He concluded different, t hat since Gapping one and a n d no t Left the Peripheral other is Deletion are i n f u e n c e d b y the p r e s e n c e of a s e n t e n t i a l phrase. Sag's Observe (130), observations t hat G a p p i n g m a y in thi s area are not comp l e t e . a p p l y a f t e r a s e n t e n t i a l s u b j e c t in the p a s s i v e v a r i a n t s of (129): _ 61 - (130) a. That the sky is b l u e h as b e e n p r o v e d last Tues d a y , and that the e a r t h is r o u n d last W e d n e s d a y . b. Fo r y o u to get the job is p r e f e r r e d by me w h e n I'm drunk-, a n d for B e t s y to get the job w h e n I 'm s o b e r . T h i s s u g g e s t s that the e x p l a n a t i o n o f (128) w h e t h e r o r n o t the s u b j e c t s are s e n t e n c e s . explanation relevance relates of which to the rule to G a p p i n g of * * Focus Assignment, the is s h o w n in S a g ' s s e c t i o n 3.5, T h e n (128) m i g h t be c o m p a r e d w i t h (131) is n o t r e l a t e d to It m a y be t h a t the (131): . a n d that p a i n t i n g , T h a t book, C h a r l e s has b oug h t , P e t e r )/i£$/ ■ ’ D at b o e k h e e f t K a r e l g e k o c h t , en d a t s c h i l d e r i j Peter One may Gapping cally entertain is the hypothesis incompatible marked with sentences, tha t the focus pattern of the f o c u s p a t t e r n o f s t y l i s t i such as (128) and (131) (but not (130)). T h i s c a u s e s some G a p p i n g s to be l o w in a c c e p t a b i l i t y . S u c h e x a m p l e s ca n n o t , therefore, be u s e d to s u b s t a n t i a t e the c l a i m that L e f t P e r i p h e r a l D e l e t i o n a n d G a p p i n g a r e d i f f e r e n t rules. - The f o u r t h a r g u m e n t r u n s as f o l l o w s (p. 207): "A f o u r t h d i f f e r e n c e b e t w e e n these t w o p r o c e s s e s , to me, can e arl i e r , (This by a in Is left that the disparity in to this to be Most intonations. clauses must speakers it s e e m s As in we noted general however, do be not in c a s e s o f l e f t - p e r i p h e r a l e l l i p s i s . the has intonational at w o r k h e r e . " their Gapped pause. such pauses possible within heard remnants separated require be highly reader some to verify.) It's of course independent explanation s y s t e m ) , but suggestive (say I take t h i s p r o s o d i c that two processes are - 62 - This ive. place a r g ument, It m a y well of the as S ag s u g g e s t s turn o ut gap. In that that is by no m e a n s c o n c l u s intonation case the is r e l a t e d prosodic to the differences c a n n o t be u s e d as p a r a m e t e r s for d i f f e r e n t rules. The fifth Peripheral observed Deletion difference relates to between the G a p p i n g a n d Left coordinator as w e l l a s . The a r g u m e n t c r u c i a l l y d e f e n d s on the a s s u m p t i o n t h a t G a p p i n g a p p l i e s to c o o r d i n a t i o n s of S only. (132) (132) Thus, * It r u n s as f o l l o w s . s h o w s that as well as c a n n o t c o n j o i n s e n t e n c e s : To m is h a p p y as well as D i c k is sad. the g r a m m a t i c a l sentence ing f o r m w i t h c o o r d i n a t e d VPs, (133) has to h a v e an u n d e r l y a n d n o t w i t h c o o r d i n a t e d Ss: (133) I spo k e to B e t s y on F r i d a y as well as to Sa n d y on S a t u rday. If G a p p i n g a p p l i e s to c o n j u n c t i o n s o f S only, a case of r e d u c t i o n by Gapping. support his hypothesis However, (133) c a n n o t be Sag does not further that G a p p i n g a p p l i e s to c o o r d i n a t i o n s of S only. H e n c e this a r g u m e n t is w i t h o u t force. This concludes tion. C l e a r l y , ingly lead the discussion of Left Peripheral Dele the a r g u m e n t s p r e s e n t e d by S a g do n o t c o n v i n c to the conclusion that two different forward r e d u c t i o n ru l e s s h o u l d be i n c o r p o r a t e d in the g r a m m a r . 3.4. CONJUNCT MOVEMENT Conjunct Movement as proposed by e.g. Ross (1967, d e r i v e s (134) f r o m the u n d e r l y i n g f o r m (135): (134) D i d y o u tell J o h n a b o u t our p l a n s or P e t e r ? H e b je J an v a n o n z e p l a n n e n v e r t e l d o f P e t e r ? (Have y o u J an o f our p l a n s t o l d or P e t e r ? ) 244) - 63 - (135) D i d y o u tell J o h n or P e t e r a b o u t o u r p l a n s ? Heb je J a n o f P e t e r v a n o n z e p l a n n e n v e r t e l d ? (Have y o u J an o r P e t e r of o ur p l a n s told ? ) It is difficult Conjunct to Movement capture in a ny the structural satisfying is g e n e r a t e d b y p h r a s e s t r u c t u r e way. rule description of If NP-coordination (136), the c o r r e s p o n d ing s t r u c t u r e is (137): (136) N P --- > NP C NP (137) NP (137) h as NP C to be restructured into (138) if C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t is to m o v e a c o n s t i t u e n t r a t h e r t h a n a s t r i n g (cf. R o s s 1967, 92, a nd P a a r d e k o o p e r 1971, In spite of this 360): restructuring, Conjunct Movement r e f e r to the i n t e r n a l s t r u c t u r e of the m o v e d item, c o n s t i t u e n t s c o n t a i n i n g a c o o r d i n a t o r can move. should be formulated with a 'm i x e d term, [C X2 ]x2 is already a the as in (139): Y l This to The rule thus specifying I n t e r n a l s t r u c t u r e of the c o n s t i t u e n t i n v o l v e d , (139) needs s i n c e only ^ serious drawback for a potential r u l e of Conjunct M o v e m e n t . Observe, derive G a pp i n g . from however, a more that fully Conjunct specified (134) t h e n d e r i v e s f r o m (140): Movement examples underlying form can by - 64 - (140) D i d y o u tell J o h n a b o u t y o u r p l a n s o r did y o u tell Peter about your plans? H e b je J a n v a n je p l a n n e n v e r t e l d of h e b je P e t e r v a n je p l a n n e n v e r t e l d ? If c o n j u n c t m o v e m e n t s t r u c t u r e s are d e r i v e d b y G a p p i n g , is for no n e e d f or the reference over, it Movement to intermediate move the turns out follow from internal that from structure certain a Gapping (137) as in constraints analysis. First to (138) (139). on there or More Conjunct observe that there is n o C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t o f verbs: (141) a. T h a t d r e s s ha s b e e n d e s i g n e d b y m y g r a n d m a and made. •X" Die jurk is o n t w o r p e n d o o r m i j n o m a en g e m a a k t . * b. He e i t h e r told P e t e r not to c o m e or w r o t e . * Hij h e e f t P e t e r of v e r t e l d dat hij n i e t h o e f d e te k o m e n o f g e s c h r e v e n . (He h a s P e t e r e i t h e r t o l d that he n o t h a d to c o m e or w r i t t e n ) U n d e r the C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t a n a l y s i s , (141) w o u l d d e r i v e f r o m (142): (142) a. That d r e s s has b e e n d e s i g n e d a n d m a d e b y my grandma. D ie jurk is o n t w o r p e n en g e m a a k t d o o r m i j n oma. b. He e i t h e r t o l d or w r o t e P e t e r n o t to come. Hij h e e f t P e t e r of v e r t e l d of g e s c h r e v e n d a t hij n i e t h o e f d e te komen. a n d a c o n d i t i o n s h o u l d be a d d e d to C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t in o r d e r to block ho w e v e r , the rule for verbal constituents. f o l l o w s a u t o m a t i c a l l y from G a p p i n g : d e l e t e s at least the verb. This fact, this r u l e a l w a y s - 65 Second, observe (143) a. (1 4 3 ): J o h n is ill a nd Peter. . J a n is ziek en Piet. b. * * J o h n are ill a nd Peter. ' J a n z i j n z i e k "en Peter. C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t d e r i v e s (143) f r o m (144) a. . (144): J o h n a n d P e t e r is ill. * b. J a n en P e t e r is ziek. J o h n a n d P e t e r are ill. - J a n en P e t e r z i j n ziek. A g r e e m e n t thus s h o u l d be o r d e r e d b e f o r e C o n j u n c t M o v e m e n t . No s such ordering to w h i c h is d i c t a t e d b y the (143) p a r a l l e l s (145) a. Gapping analysis, according (145). J o h n is ill a nd P e t e r J a n is ziek en P e t e r i é / i i é Ji. b. J o h n are ill a n d P e t e r $.)(•£/ i t t • J a n z i j n z i e k en P e t e r Third, observe that Conjunct / i,i- i Ji. Movement sentences which contain a negation: (146) J o h n a n d M a r y d i d n ' t w i n a prize. J a n en M a r i e w o n n e n g e e n p r i j s . (Jan a n d M a r i e w o n no priz e ) (147) * * J o h n d i d n ' t w i n a p r i z e a n d Mary. J a n w o n g e e n p r i j s en Marie. (Jan w o n no p r i z e a n d Mari e ) cannot apply to - 66 - How such a d e r i v a t i o n s h o u l d be excluded under Movement assumption remains unclear. the Conjunct In the G a p p i n g a n a l y s i s , (147) is u n g r a m m a t i c a l for the s ame r e a s o n (148) is: (148) * J o h n d i d n ' t w i n the car, a n d M a r y jdi ( d p i / t h e free trip. * It is " J a n w o n de a u t o n i e t e n M a r i e a general feature deletion rules), that entails that of Gapping negative purported de v a k a n t i e r e l s (and p r e s u m a b l y particles Conjunct of all n e v e r de l e t e . Movement examples This can be d e s c r i b e d b y (and t h e i r d i s t r i b u t i o n e x p l a i n e d b y c o n s t r a i n t s on) Gapping, coordinate an d that structures there is no n e e d into (138). f o r r e s t r u c t u r i n g of Notice finally t hat the p r o p o s e d a n a l y s i s of the s o - c a l l e d c o n j u n c t m o v e m e n t e x a m p l e s as cases remnant. of Gapping This goes against (1976) and Zwarts leaves tw o rem n a n t s . assumption, we may and conclude that, tion, the it is implies (1978), recent who Since grant that this r ule may proposals suggest t hat leave one e.g. Sag by, Gapping always t h e y o f f e r n o r a t i o n a l e f o r t his the rule the licence allowed here together with Backward Conjunction Reduc only rul e of coordination r e d u c t i o n in the grammar. F O O T N O T E S TO C H A P T E R 1 1. F o r the D u t c h o b s e r v a t i o n s in this s e c t i o n I am o b l i g e d to Paardekooper 2. It seems reasonable projections only, e.g. (1971, of 365). to lexical restrict X categories in (10) (N, A, a nd P, V, in v i e w o f the u n g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of (i). (11) to and Q) - 67 (i) He is e a t i n g a p p l e s a n d or n o r pea r s . * Hi j eet a p p e l s en o f n o c h per e n . C o o r d i n a t o r s are n o n l e x i c a l c a t e g o r i e s , ( c f . C h o m s k y 1965, 3. T h i s argument wa s and published mentation 212, fn.9). presented in Z o n n e v e l d can be and cannot conjoin at the (1978). construed f or TIN The meeting of 1976, same l i n e o f a r g u German, and perhaps for o t h e r E u r o p e a n V e r b - s c r a m b l i n g l a n g u a g e s as wel l . 4. M a n a s t e r - R a m e r pro and con Dutch and Neijt (1978). context (1978), SOV or G e rman, a as review an argument sin c e of previous arguments the u n d e r l y i n g w o r d o r d e r presents This as well, in SVO alleged counterargument is Neijt relevant (1978) in the for to present is a p r e - p u b l i c a t i o n o f s e c t i o n 1.1. o f t h i s chap t e r . Manaster-Ramer calls attention to the following example (p. 260): / % (i) * J a n en lacht e n huilt. (John b o t h l a u g h s a n d cries) an d c o n t i n u e s as follows: " N e i j t 1s huiit has account a re suggested constituent Vs. But won't constituents. that types the work because Neijt the r i g h t to lacht and communication) c o n d i t i o n a l l o w s o n l y some conjo i n , grammatlcality clearly (personal of specifically (12) makes ible. (12) J a n zal e n l a c h e n en huil e n . 'John w i l l b o t h l a u g h a n d cry.' V P s but not that imposs _ 68 - W i t h o u t p r o v i d i n g a n a n a l y s i s o f D u t c h c o n j u n c t i o n s here (see Manaster-Ramer (forthcoming)). I am surely justi f i e d in r e j e c t i n g N e i j t ' s a r g u m e n t as u n c o m p e l l i n g ." As M a n a s t e r - R a m e r notices, able: t wo a s s u m p t i o n s are i m a g i n e - the c o o r d i n a t i o n en l acht en h u i l t is e i t h e r a c o o r d i n a t i o n of Vs, or a c o o r d i n a t i o n o f VPs. If it is a c o o r *•=1_ d i n a t i o n o f Vs, n o t h i n g f o l l o w s f r o m my a n a l y s i s . It is impossible, tion 1. of however, t h a t en l a c h t en h u i l t is a c o o r d i n a Vs in v i e w o f the a r g u m e n t s Furthermore, VP-adverbs, in that case such as h a r d it presented cannot ('lo u d l y ' ) be cannot in s e c t i o n explained why be p l a c e d o u t side o f the i n i t i a l c o o r d i n a t i o n : (ii) * ..., om d a t J a n h a r d en la c h t en hui l t . (..., b e c a u s e J o h n l o u d l y b o t h l a u g h s a n d cries) O n the of o t h e r hand, VPs, the ter-Ramer if en la c h t e n h u i l t pattern follows of quite is a c o o r d i n a t i o n grammaticalness naturally. Verb by Manas- Preposing cited is i m p o s s i b l e in (i), w h i c h is s t r u c t u r e d r o u g h l y as (iii). ;i i i ) Ja n lac h t E n l a c h t a nd en h u i l t therefore fronts cannot verbs, be n ot n ot p o s s i b l e either; do n ot f o r m one V - n o d e t o g e t h e r a n d fronted VPs). (v): is possible (cf. in one swoop Across-the-board (Verb Fronting movement is the V - n o d e s are d i f f e r e n t . In (12), on the o t h e r hand, zal huilt (i v ) ), a c r o s s - t h e - b o a r d m o v e m e n t of and this application yields - 69 - (iv) Ja n zal lachen zal huilen (v) NP J an Therefore, sentence I do not challenges se e SOV how as the the grammaticality underlying word of this order of Dutch. 5. T h i s c o n d i t i o n o f W i l l i a m s ' a f a c t o r as f o l lows: d e f i n e s the w e l l - f o r m e d n e s s of "If F is a f a c t o r a n d C a c o o r d i n a t e structure containing conjuncts . . .C , t h e n f o r F to be a w e l l - f o r m e d f a c t o r the f o l l o w i n g m u s t hold: „[ £ F a n d „] £ i i that L £ F a n d Li 6. W i l l i a m s (1977, F, then for all presents (i) i, if f or any i1, it m u s t be the case r ] £ F. 1 102) in o r d e r to i l l u s t r a t e that G a p p i n g c a n n o t a p p l y a c r o s s s e n t e n c e s in a d i s c o u r s e . (i) A: B: D i d Sa m go to the s t o r e ? * No, Bill Some comments First, observe are to the s u p e r m a r k e t . in order, however, tha t G a p p i n g c a n n o t which undermine apply of an i n t e r r o g a t i v e a n d a d e c l a r a t i v e s e n t e n c e : (ii) D i d Sa m go to the store a n d Bill i i i t t to the s u p e r m a r k e t . (i). to c o o r d i n a t i o n s - 70 - Second, (i) the is introduction clearly relevant of the negative particle to the application of No in Gapping: (iii) is d e f i n i t e l y b e t t e r t h a n (i): (iii) A: S a m wen t to the store, B: If the (And) Bill vMjii! to the s u p e r m a r k e t . gapped sentence negative particle, is outside of the scope of the G a p p i n g is p e r f e c t : (iv) A: D i d Sam go to the s t o r e ? B: No. A: J2^0 Bill ¿gS to the s u p e r m a r k e t ? B: Yes. 7. T h i s c l a i m c a n be c l a r i f i e d as fol l o w s . In o r d e r to d e r i v e (82), let us a s s u m e that the e x t e n sive f o r m u l a t i o n o f G a p p i n g a p p l i e s i t e r a t i v e l y f r o m right to left: !i ) [[[NP V NP] and [NP V NP]] or [[NP V NP] \ ..... 1 st application: application: The second and erate the [NP V NP]]] / -V' 'U' 2n d a p p l i c a t i o n : \____________ 3 and » ________________________»I 'V' t h ird a p p l i c a t i o n s c o m b i n e d , ungrammatical (83), and t h ere however, is no gen non-adhoc w a y to b l o c k this c o m b i n a t i o n o f a p p l i c a t i o n s . Alternatively, one m a y a s s u m e the f o l l o w i n g a p p l i c a t i o n s : that (82) is g e n e r a t e d by - 71 - ( ii ) [[[ NP V NP] a nd [NP V NP]] or [[NP V NP] \ ________________________________ U______ / 1 st and [NP V NP])] " " 'U' application: 2nci a p p l i c a t i o n : 3^ application: In this yield no case, the fir s t the u n g r a m m a t i c a l non-adhoc cations (in (1978), cf. way to fact and (83), exclude this th i r d is a applications a nd a g a i n this th e r e s e e m s to be combination problem combined noticed of by appli Williams (79) a nd (80) above). O b s e r v e that the s e c o n d a p p l i c a t i o n in (i) a n d the t h i r d application in (ii) applications yield (iii) are (iii), the # [[[John i n v i t e d Sue] or [[Max problematic ones: another ungrammatical Sue] and and th e s e sentence: [Max i n v i t e d Mary]] [John i n v i t e d Mary]]] In v i e w of th e s e p r o b l e m s of r u l e a p p l i c a t i o n the e x t e n s i ve f o r m u l a t i o n of G a p p i n g c a n n o t be m o t i v a t e d b y s e n t e n c e s s u c h as: (iv) * J o h n i n v i t e d Sue, P e t e r k i s s e d Mary, Max and Betsy. sin ce if (i v ) c a n n o t be g e n e r a t e d b e c a u s e of the s t r u c t u r al description of the rule, (82) (ii)) c a n n o t be g e n e r a t e d either. cation of the m i s s i n g part (cf. structures Therefore, of g a p p e d (i) and the i d e n t i f i sentences is a p r o b l e m not to be s o l v e d by the f o r m u l a t i o n o f the rule. - 72 - 8. Cf. Sag (1976, 115), who advocates a small-scale formula of VP-deletion. 9. F r o m this . analysis interpretive ru l e s applicability. follows as that transformations regards Transformations need t h e - b o a r d fashion, (i) it differ and across-the-board to a p p l y in an a c r o s s cf.: What, did H a r r y e a t e. a n d Bill d r i n k e,? ______ ____ / 1______ __________ ƒ! ( i i ) What, did H a r r y eat e. a n d Bill d r i n k b e e r ? * 1 ::__________ / x I n t e r p r e t i v e rul e s such as P a s s i v e a n d I t - r e p l a c e m e n t n e e d not a p p l y in an a c r o s s - t h e - b o a r d fashion, cf.: (iii) C u r v a l . hit J u l i e a n d w a s p u n c h e d e. b y A d o n i s . 1__________________________________ / x (iv) The F e w w r i t e r s , are b o t h e x p l i c i t a n d e a s y to r e a d e. ^ 1____________________________________ _______ / 1 latter thus p r e t i v e rules, resemble clear-cut instances of inter such as R e f l e x i v i z a t i o n : (v) John, f ed the dog a n d w a s h e d h i m s e l f . . \J:___________________________________ / 1 10. H o w e v e r , 1973, 376). cf. the Predicate Deletion Constraint (Kuno C H A P T E R 2. The Rule of Gapping This section chapter is reconsiders subdivided the (1975). three parts. formulation fo r E n g l i s h b y H a n k a m e r doen into (1973), Partly with of the Stillings the a i d of K u n o rule The of fi r s t Gapping (1975) a n d L a n g e n (1976), it w i l l be f o u n d that n o n e of these t h r e e p r o p o s a l s a d e q u a t e l y e x p l a i n s the of phenomenon Gapping in English. Th e second c o n c e r n s o u r o w n f o r m u l a t i o n o f the rule of- G a p p i n g . will receive specific restrictions. required only. on tion. follow This the a very general will basis from is claimed independently with th a t The rule little or no the restrictions motivated constraints be d e m o n s t r a t e d p a r t l y in the t h i r d s e c t i o n of Following It formulation, section the Sag requirement (1976), of it w i l l recoverability be argued of th a t dele several f e a t u r e s o f G a p p i n g are p r e d i c t a b l e g i v e n a p r e c i s e f o r m u l a t i o n o f the n o t i o n o f "ide n t i t y " . 1. E A R L I E R R U L E S OF G A P P I N G 1.1. H A N K A M E R « S U N A C C E P T A B I L I T Y The unclear precise in formulation Hankamer (1971). o f the However, ru l e o f G a p p i n g is left in H a n k a m e r (1973, 18) the a u t h o r p r e s e n t s the f o l l o w i n g f o r m u l a t i o n : (1) G a p p i n g N P X A Z a n d NP X B Z ---- 5» N P X A Z a n d NP B w h e r e A a n d B are n o n i d e n t i c a l m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s . This rule r efers, formula is p o s s i b l y due to Ross, to w h o m H a n k a m e r t h o u g h the n o t i o n o f " m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n c y " is c e r t a i n - 74 - ly due to H a n k a m e r . It is d e f i n e d as ( H a n k a m e r 1973, 18, fn. 2) : "A 'major constituent ately q constituent' of a given sentence Sq is a e i t h e r i m m e d i a t e l y d o m i n a t e d by S Q or i m m e d i dominated by VP, which is i m m e d i a t e l y d o m i n a t e d by ii 0’ Let us r e f e r to the c o n d i t i o n that the r e m n a n t s o f G a p p i n g be major constituents as condition functions rem n a n t s . It p r e v e n t s the as Major an (1) Constituent effective Condition. constraint This on p o s s i b l e f r o m d e l e t i n g m o r e t h a n a l l o w e d in (2), f o r i n stance: (2) J o h n t o o k B i l l ' s r e d s h o e s an d Max I K B i l l ' s blu e hat. ‘ 4 blu e hat. I The f ocu s hat. o f H a n k a m e r 1s a r t i c l e (1973, 29) is the fol lowing No-Ambiguity Condition: (3) The N o - A m b i g u i t y C o n d i t i o n A n y a p p l i c a t i o n o f G a p p i n g w h i c h w o u l d y i e l d an o u t p u t s t r u c t u r e i d e n t i c a l to a s t r u c t u r e d e r i v a b l e b y G a p p i n g f r o m a n o t h e r s o u r c e , b u t w i t h the "gap" at the l eft e x t r e m i t y [of the g a p p e d c o n j u n c t ] is di s a l l o w e d . As pointed out by H a n k a m e r , transderivational derive strings the N o - A m b i g u i t y C o n d i t i o n is a constraint. such as (4), Because the c l u d e s the s u p e r f i c i a l l y i d e n t i c a l , it is possible but d i f f e r e n t l y s t r u c t u r ed s t r i n g s in (5). (4) a. B ill e x p e c t s H a r r y to f i n d the w a y to the party, and ¥>ift / b. to No-Ambiguity Condition ex Sue to f i n d the w a y home. J a c k w a n t s M i k e to w a s h h i m s e l f and ^ A r n i e to s have h i m s e l f . 75 - _ c. M a x w a n t e d T e d to p e r s u a d e A l e x to get los t a n d Walt d. I r a ti>/ &£t / . M a x w a n t e d to put the e g g p l a n t o n the table, an d H / M t H a r v e y in the sink. (5) a. Bill e x p e c t s H a r r y to f i n d the w a y to the part y , a n d Sue to f i n d the w a y home. b. * J a c k w a n t s M i k e to w a s h h i m s e l f , Arnie a nd to s h ave h i m s e l f . c. * M a x w a n t e d T e d to p e r s u a d e A l e x to get lost, Wa l t Ira t<b d. * M a x w a n t e d to p u t the e g g p l a n t on the table, Harvey an d t H W t i H i t / t4>$t ■ an d ! t t i I H M t M t in the sink. ! t<t 1 Th e N o - A m b i g u i t y C o n d i t i o n c h a r a c t e r i z e s an i n t r i g u i n g set of d a t a in a r e v e a l i n g way. accept th i s devices s u c h as e.g. f i l t e r s vs. vs. they T h i s is n o t s u f f i c i e n t , transderivational rule global r ule types, in t r a n s f o r m a t i o n s vs. ordering and formulations involve condition general of rule the r e w r i t i n g r u les, obligatoriness, rule conditions, simplifications a n d if, m o r e o v e r , however, grammar. are in the to New or or t r a c e s a c c e p t e d if format of other e a c h s p e c i m e n o f the n e w d e v i c e is i n d e p e n d e n t l y m o t i v a t e d by s o l v i n g p r o b l e m s w i t h m o r e tha n one rule or p r i n c i p l e . T h e s e h e a v y r e s t r i c t i o n s o n n e w d e v i c e s a re j u s t i f i e d as long as one takes learnability controlled by of linguistics natural an underlying less fre e w h e e l i n g ciated coherence as an language, attempt i.e. reality as rather to e x p l a i n an than the enterprise a more or c h a r a c t e r i z a t i o n o f an i n t u i t i v e l y a p p r e between linguistic data. Stillings (1975) a n d L a n g e n d o e n (1975) a t t e m p t to r e f o r m u l a t e the N o - A m b i g u i t y Condition however, in more acceptable terms. Both a n d it s e e m s i n s t r u c t i v e to s h o w why. attempts fail, _ 76 - 1.2. S T I L L I N G S 1975 As n o t e d above, t hat led Stillings Hankamer (1975) ungrammatical it is the d i f f e r e n c e b e t w e e n to makes propose the sentences the observation of (5) t hat moment the initial f o r m u l a t i o n of G a p ping, subject As gap in the a NP ( d i s r e g a r d i n g for a more (6) restricted (p. 257): -- NP V * C 2 NP), Condition. contained she t h e r e f o r e p r o p o s e s (6) G a p p i n g 1 the originally c o n s t i t u e n t , w h e r e a s the g a p in (4) di d n o t a (4) a n d (5) No-Ambiguity {AND, OR} 3 NP V* C 4 4 5 5 7 . 0 In thi s rule, C is a c o n s t i t u e n t v a r i a b l e , d e f i n e d as f o l l o w s (p. 252): ' "Multiple be occurrences expanded t hey occur of the constituent variable C must in the sam e w a y w h e n the r ule s c h e m a in w h i c h is expanded into one of the rules which it a b b r e v i a t e s ." By this definition, rule (5) is an a b b r e v i a t i o n o f the l o w i n g set of rules: (7) a. N P V * S {AND, O R } 4 NP V * S 0 b. N P V* NP {AND, OR} NP V * NP c. N P V* P P {AND, OR} N P V * PP etc. 4 fol - 77 - If C is n ot e x p a n d e d twice in the sam e way, application of Gapping is ungrammatical the r e s u l t of the as can be observed from (8):1 (8) a, F r e d e a t s at A r b y ' s , an d m y b r o t h e r - i n - l a w i i - t i p i c k l e d beets. b. * P r i c k l y p e a r s g r o w s lowly, a n d A s i a t i c D a y f l o w e r s in L e v e r e t t , The notation variable which (used contains allowed 253), to V * in f o r the verbs delete a (6) represents fi r s t only. set time The of a p a r t i c u l a r type in B r e s n a n 1971, rule adjacent of Gapping verbs of 266), one is thereby (Stillings 1975, cf.: (9) Abodeefa attempted to learn steen" and Miles to play "Klactoveedsed- to l e a r n to p l a y " K o k o " . to p l a y "Koko". I m m u á i u n u u / u / i u í "Koko". By this evades restriction the on the derivation of contents of the (5.), a n d o b v i a t e s gap, Stillings the n e e d f o r the No-Ambiguity Condition. Th e r e are o t h e r t h a n V, preverbal cases where s u c h as: adverbs (cf. p o s t v e r b a l c l i t i c s (cf. the the gap involves constituents i n f i n i t i v e p a r t i c l e to (cf. (10),. Jackendoff 1971, (11), J a c k e n d o f f 1971, (9)); 23); and 24), as in: (10) a. S i m o n q u i c k l y d r o p p e d the g o l d a n d J a c k (hMiW / the di a m o n d s . b. M a x s o m e t i m e s b e a t s h i s w i f e a n d T e d I M & t i h i s dog. (11) P a u l S c h a c h t e r h a s i n f o r m e d me that the b a s i c o r d e r in T a g a l o g a nd r e l a t e d l a n g u a g e s is VOS; Ives Goddard / íi/ytúfú’i fi/ti't that the u n m a r k e d o r d e r in A l g o n k i a n is OVS; an d G u y C a r d e n f í é i i W f W i á # ( ¿ / W o r d e r in A l e u t is OSV. t h a t the b a s i c H ere, Stillings assumes restructuring i nto not mention AUX-V restructuring explicitly, (12). (She does b u t it is in line w i t h he r a p p r o a c h of n o n - V G a p p i n g in g e n e r a l . ) This assumption successfully predicts m e n t i o n e d h a v e to be p a r t of the gap, t hat the elements just like V, and c a n n o t b e l o n g to the set of p o s s i b l e remnants: (9') * A b o d e e f a a t t e m p t e d to l e a r n to p l a y " K l a c t o v e e d s e d st e e n " and M i l e s (10') a. u t m n a u 1 e a r n to p l a y "Koko" I I t i k t i h J p l a y "Koko" S i m o n q u i c k l y d r o p p e d the g o l d a n d J a c k s u d d e n l y the diam o n d s . b. * ' Max sometimes beats his wife and Ted frequently hi s dog. (11') Paul S c h a c h t e r ha s i n f o r m e d me t h a t the b a s i c o r d e r in T a g a l o g a n d r e l a t e d l a n g u a g e s is VOS; Goddard Ives tha t the u n m a r k e d o r d e r in A l g o n k i a n is OVS; and Guy Carden $$$/ me that the b a s i c o r d e r in A l e u t is OSV. Less promising full PP, candidates although ( J a c k e n d o f f 1971, such 24), f o r ' r e s t r u c t u r i n g are restructuring is full NP and required for (13) s t r u c t u r e d as in (14): (13) a. J o h n w r i t e s p o e t r y in the g a r d e n , and Max in the b a thr o o m . b, C h a r l i e w e n t i n t o the b e d r o o m at 5:30, ■ at 5:31. and L o l a _ 79 - The restructuring approach breaks down definitely in cases where Gapping involves constituents not adjacent those to the verb: (15) a. J a c k b e g g e d E l s i e to get m a r r i e d , and Wil f r e d Phoebe b. I l e a r n e d to ride last week, and Bill Mi-iiW'k to r ow W i t ! c. I t o l d Sue a b o u t the party, a n d Bill M U Martha d. Joe c o v e r e d the f l o o r w i t h red p a i n t , and Alice the w a l l s u w t u i u n t . e. Joe p a i n t e d h i s b o a t red, a n d A l i c e h e r c a r f O.. f. H a n k hi t a h o m e run o n T h u r s d a y , Ifiit a s i n g l e In order to generate the rule of "Truncation", these sentences, deleting ents. The rule is left u n f o r m u l a t e d . (15) are derived and Maris ■ from Stillings conjunct introduces fi n a l constitu The r e d u c e d s e n t e n c e s in their, full u n d e r l y i n g forms via (16), the T r u n c a t i o n stage: (16) a. J a c k b e g g e d E l s i e to get m a r r i e d , and Wilfred b e g g e d P h o e b e t</> I l e a r n e d to ride l a s t week, , and Bill learned to ro w c. I told Sue a b o u t the party , Martha d. * Joe c o v e r e d the f l o o r w i t h r e d p a i n t , c o v e r e d the w a l l s e. a n d B i l l told . * and Alice . Joe p a i n t e d h i s boat red, a n d A l i c e p a i n t e d her car f U . f. H a n k hi t a h o m e ru n o n T h u r s d a y , a n d M a r i s hit a single . - 80 - Ho w e v e r , for as (16d) obligatory (15e) are Truncation tively of and real examples does no t interesting these (16e) show, constituents. cases, Truncation This of implies multiple but that is t h a t the impossible (15d) gapping, c o v e r all i n s t a n c e s o f conclusion is that and and (15). that A compara it d o e s n o t c o v e r any rule of Gapping must be f o r m u l a t e d so as to d e r i v e the w h o l e set in (15). In f a v o r of h e r a n a l y s i s S t i l l i n g s presents (17), a set of m u l t i p l e ga p e x a m p l e s w h i c h m u s t d e f i n i t e l y be excl u d e d : (17) a. A1 w a s c l e a r l y i n t e n t on t e l l i n g A l i c e to b u y the lettuce and Alfred Jim U l U i l i U l l i t i U i . b. N a n c y t h o u g h t M i k e f o o l i s h f o r e v e n t a l k i n g to Sally and Cindy Alfonse t<t>t! iii iy U lU M /U /U U f. c. * J o h n a s k e d G e o r g e to be the one to i n f o r m M a r y of Ellington's death and Fred d. Sam The b o x c e r t a i n l y c o n t a i n e d t h u m b t a c k s b e f o r e M a r t y s p i l l e d t h e m a n d the c a r t o n pins e. * I p l a n to t a l k to M a r y a w e e k f r o m n e x t T u e s d a y an d J o h n i>t m / u / t m tM i M i , f. * to F r e d - A r t h u r p u t h i s b o a c o n s t r i c t o r U n d e r the m a t t r e s s at 80 W. W a r r e n a n d Be r n i e $ plywood / 1$4 / 0 0 / ¥ Uy&f Mi i ■ These examples Hankamer cussed in are (1971), no t excluded an d S a g section 2). (1976) However, e x c l u d e d in S t i l l i n g s 1 f r a m e w o r k . by the Gapping analyses of (whose p r o p o s a l w i l l be d i s it is not clear how In p a r t i c u l a r , (17) is she p r e s e n t s no r e a s o n w h y T r u n c a t i o n c a n n o t a p p l y to it. In c h a p t e r 3 it will in be shown that f o r m u l a t i o n of G a pping, (17) is fact irrelevant to the but p e r t a i n s to the s c o p e of r u l e s in - 81 - g e neral. This strengthens the conclusion that (15) are ca s e s of m u l t i p l e Gapping. 1.3. L A N G E N D O E N 1975 Just as Stillings alternative to (1’ 975), Hankamer's Langendoen (1975) transderivational p r e s e n t s an constraint by m e a n s of a d i r e c t r e s t r i c t i o n o n the gap: (18) The n o n l e f t - p e r i p h e r a l N P c o n d i t i o n C o o r d i n a t i o n D e l e t i o n c a n n o t a p p l y so as to d e l e t e n o n l e f t - p e r i p h e r a l s t r i n g s that c o n t a i n N P . No doubt an a t t r a c t i v e feature predicts ungrammatical gappings ripheral gap. si nce either contains a The NP. left-peripheral, (20') examples the internal in g ap condition irrespective (19) or cases and the where (20) left-pe are excluded gap are the r e d u c t i o n is g r a m m a t i c a l , deleted cf. NPs (19') and 113 - 4). yi&ii/ S u s a n and yesterday. M a x w a n t e d T e d to p e r s u a d e A l e x to see Mary, and b. * W a l t f<j>I Ira m/tfi&tf. M a x w a n t e d T e d to p e r s u a d e A l e x to see Mary, a nd W a l t t<t> I 11<!>I (19') M a x sent S a l l y the m e s s e n g e r l a s t week, yi&t-/ Susan yesterday. Walt same examples as S t i l l i n g s ' ing-cum-restructuring-and-Truncation 1971, 24): (cf., and Ira. The N o n l e f t - p e r i p h e r a l NP C o n d i t i o n runs a g r o u n d , the Ira. and (20') M a x w a n t e d T e d to p e r s u a d e A l e x to see Mary, precisely it a all those M a x sent S a l l y the m e s s e n g e r l a s t week, (20) a. is t h a t of right-peripheral In ( L a n g e n d o e n 1975, (19) of this however, on a n a l y s i s of Ga p p again, Jackendoff - 82 - (21) a. J o h n w r i t e s p o e t r y in the g a r d e n a n d M a x in the b a t h r o o m . D . A r i z o n a e l e c t e d G o l d w a t e r S e n a t o r and Pennsylvania Schweiker $ $ \ . c. J o h n g ave M a r y a n i c k e l and S u s a n Harvey • F o r t h e s e p h e n o m e n a t here does no t s e e m to be a s o l u t i o n that doe s not meet the problems discussed in the preceding section. Moreover, is acceptable Gr a m m a r . As although its L a n g e n d o e n 's o nly such, if it the isolated Nonleft-peripheral is taken condition character as a part is -hard NP Condition of Universal to criticize, d oe s c e r t a i n l y n o t c o u n t in f a v o r o f it. 1.4. K U N O 1976 Kuno amples section (1976) to 1.1. parallels presents H a n k a m e r 's in All these Dutch a set of No-Ambiguity interesting Condition counterexamples (cf. Kuno (1976, have 306) counterex discussed in straightforward for the English e x a m p l e s ): (22) My b r o t h e r v i s i t e d J a p a n in 1960, and my sister i U i t U i i U U in 1961. Mi jn b r o e r b e z o c h t J a p a n in 1 9 6 0 en mi jn zus in 1961. (23) H a r r y t o l d this s t o r y to h i s m o t h e r , a n d T om tshii! i t i i i to h i s father. H a r r i e v e r t e l d e dit v e r h a a l a an z i j n m o e d e r en Tom i i t t £t 44 / i t t H i M a a n z l j n v ader. T h e s e s e n t e n c e s are g r a m m a t i c a l , a l t h o u g h v a r i a n t s e x i s t w i t h a left peripheral a n o m a l o u s ): gap (w h i c h fo r (23) are semantically - 83 - (22') M y b r o t h e r v i s i t e d J a p a n in 196 0 and my s i s t e r in 1961 . M i j n b r o e r b e z o c h t J a p a n in 196 0 en $ (23') i m i j n z u s in 1961. l H a r r y to l d this s t ory to h i s m o t h e r , and y a t t i ! t i t i - T o m »to h i s father. H a r r y v e r t e l d e dit v e r h a a l a an z i j n m o e d e r en T o m a a n z i j n v a der. w t u m t u w Moreover, that factors Kuno's most important outside syntax of observations make may influence m a t i c a l i t y j u d g m e n t s o n s e n t e n c e s of thi s type. the lexical content crucial role (25), and of the NPs the gram- F o r i n s t ance, seems to play a (p.307). C o m p a r e the a- a n d b - i n s t a n c e s o f (24), (26), which parallel a n d (5) above. (24) a. involved clear Hankamer's basic set in (4) . J o h n b e l i e v e s M a r y to be g u i l t y , and Tom to be i nnoce n t . b. O f the p e o p l e p o lled, to be gu i l t y , 8 0 % b e l i e v e the P r e s i d e n t and 20% IMi (to be) innocent. (i r r e p r o d u c a b l e in D u t c h ) (25) a. J a c k a s k e d Mik e to w a s h hi m s e l f , a n d Sue M U * / M M to s h a v e h i m s e l f . J a c k v r o e g M i k e z i c h z e l f te w a s s e n en Sue z i c h z e l f te scher e n . b. 5 0 % of h i s c o n s t i t u e n t s a s k e d the S e n a t o r to v o t e for the bill, a n d 2 5% to v o t e a g a i n s t it. '50% v r o e g h e t k a m e r l i d v o o r de w e t te s t e m m e n en 2 5 % ertegen (50% a s k e d the s e n a t o r f o r the bil l a n d 2 5 % &.4M4- / '¡hto vot e there-against - 84 - (26) a. *• M a x w a n t e d T e d to p e r s u a d e A l e x to see M a r y and Walt Ira M I tii/^iti, 9 'Max w i l d e T ed A l e x l a t e n o v e r h a l e n o m M a r y op te z o e k e n en W a l t i i f t t i Ira M in u u iu m tiiw iu iu iM ii. (Max w a n t e d T e d A l e x let p e r s u a d e f o r M a r y u p to l o o k a nd W a l t Ira u tu m iu tm tiiM iu iu it.) b. S o m e R e p u b l i c a n s want F o r d to r u n f o r the P r e s i d e n c y in 1976, a n d o t h e r s iii-iif R e a g a n U ltU ltM ltM I'tU M M M ilU llM l. Sommige Republikeinen willen Ford lijsttrekker l a t e n w o r d e n en a n d e r e n i i f t t i v i R e a g a n U m tU tU t/IH H /M U M . (Some R e p u b l i c a n s w a n t F o r d c a n d i d a t e let be a n d o t h e r s iii-iit R e a g a n u m .u u iu tm .) In the same vein, ents containing if the c o n t e x t c l e a r l y s h o w s that c o n s t i t u old information have been gapp e d , c o n s t i t u e n t s w i t h n ew i n f o r m a t i o n are l e f t b e h i n d , is grammatical irrespective of the lexical whereas the o u t p u t content of the NPs. K u n o (p . 308) d e m o n s t r a t e s t h i s by p r e s e n t i n g a qu e s t i o n , w h i c h p r e c e d e s the g a p p e d a nswer: (27) a. Q : W i t h w h a t did J o h n a n d B i l l h i t Ma r y ? A: J o h n h it M a r y w i t h a s t i c k and B i l l n t i w i w i t h a belt. Q: W a a r m e e s l o e g e n J a n en Bill M a r i e ? ( W h e r e w i t h hit J a n a n d B i l l M a r i e ? ) A: J a n s l o e g M a r i e m e t e e n s t o k e n Bill m e t e e n riem. b. Q: W h e r e d id M a x a n d H a r v e y w a n t to p u t the eggplant? A: M a x w a n t e d to put the e g g p l a n t on the ta b l e a n d Harvey t<i>/i>M/ in the sink. - 85 - (27) b . (c o n t .) Q: W a a r w i l d e n Max eri H a r r y de k o m k o m m e r p l a n t neerzetten? (Where w a n t e d M ax a n d H a r r y the e g g p l a n t (t o ) p u t ? ) A: M ax w i l d e de k o m k o m m e r p l a n t op t a f e l z e t t e n en Harry i iftM / M / f M t M M t i l i - M op h e t a a n r e c h t M itU U U . (Max w a n t e d the e g g p l a n t on table Harry The implication vered for by in the of Kuno's o b s e r v a t i o n is that N o - A m b i g u i t y C o n d i t i o n are n o t s yntax. (to) p u t a n d in the s i n k The alternatives presented the facts c o to be a c c o u n t e d by Stillings and L a n g e n d o e n are s y n t a c t i c a l l y s u p e r f l u o u s . A l t h o u g h it is e a s y to be be wise that catch after the up the event, devices with the the g e n e r a l proposed facts by conclusion seems Stillings presented and to Langendoen by Hankamer, but lack that " [m]odern linguist c o ncerned- w i t h o b s e r v a t i o n a l adequacy" i n d e p e n d e n t s u p p o r t in a s t r i k i n g way. 2. D E S C R I P T I V E A D E Q U A C Y Chomsky's criticism ics has been disguises a largely significant study of by Saussure De distributional and (1964, problem. phenomena Bloomfield struction of categories, 29) was Let us along suppose the directed lines toward to since be largely this c o u l d adequacy. valued as the the con e a c h o f w h i c h c o u l d be c h e c k e d m o r e or less d i r e c t l y by its o wn set of o b s e r v a t i o n s . had that suggested concerned with Such studies observational ade q u a c y , be s e e n as a d i r e c t m e a s u r e f o r d e s c r i p t i v e The c l o s e n e s s to o b s e r v a t i o n a l a hallmark of s c i e n t i f i c reality was probably "certainty", a safeguard a g a i n s t not d i r e c t l y c o n t r o l l a b l e s p e c u l a t i o n . Th e s e very into d i s r e p u t e . virtues caused this type of study to fall T a x o n o m i e s of o b s e r v a t i o n s w i t h o u t u n e x p e c t e d - 86 - implications, incapable m a t i c a l p a t t e r n s w ere which the ten c e s fluent he tical ha s speaker no t notions to anticipate the ju d g e s heard should the before. have a influ e n c e . ed". The In no t be diversity brief, set-up completely of grammaticality By these harmless gram of they an d o u t l o o k o f different be sen gramma each Grammatical notions implications, should of standards generalizations, r e d u c i b l e to its o w n set of o b s e r v a t i o n s . would variety i n a d e q u a t e to p o r t r a y the c o m p e t e n c e by d ue to m utual "independently motivat the C h o m s k y a n a p p r o a c h that any a t t e m p t is so to see it as a c o n t i n u a t i o n of " A m e r i c a n " l i n g u i s t i c s s e e m s a m e n t a l e x e r c i s e of a doubtful kind, certain crucial And, deemed to m i s s the m a j o r p o i n t a n d to m i s t a k e characteristics fo r additional if e v e n u n d i s p u t a b l y c l e a r o b s e r v a t i o n s c a n o f f e r only a t e n t a t i v e c h e c k on c a t e g o r i e s and rules, new properties. hallmark of motivation", T he linguistic soundness, it is c l e a r t h a t the that is: "independent is i n d i s p e n s a b l e . relevance of any s p e c i f i c p r o p o s a l is t e n t a t i v e a n d o n l y i n t u i t i v e l y a p p r e c i a t e d as " r e v e a l i n g " or " s i g n i f i c a n t " . This is a phenomena general pr o b l e m , as well. It which is n o t derived by phrasal conjunction, are be assumed (for to respect to G a p ping, that S t i l l i n g s the exists a priori or h o w m a n y relevance see c h a p t e r for 1). the Gapping c l e a r w h a t s h o u l d be of reduction these rules rules with It is w o r t h i l l u s t r a t i n g (1975) an d S a g (1976) w e r e w e l l - a w a r e of this. S t i l l i n g s a d m i t s of h e r rule (p. 270) that "w h i l e it which are above , doe s not generate grammatical, at least it e.g., all of the sentences generates only gapped (Al-6) sentences i.e. grammatical (16) gapped s e n t e n c e s ." Th i s view contrasts as f o l l o w s "The (1976, Sag's, who summarizes his position 279): proposed analysis overgenerates we h a v e argued, Bo t h p o s i t i o n s to c l a i m naturally claims with that imply further hypotheses. the g a p p e d from t hat considerably, the which, is a d e s i r a b l e r e s u l t , " some other incorrect Stillings is f o r c e d s e n t e n c e s n o t g e n e r a t e d w ill f o l l o w independently g a p s w h i c h his motivated rule. Sag r ule g e n e r a t e s are - 87 - filtered oases, ou t th e r e by independently is n o a p r o i r i motivated principles. In b o t h o b s e r v a t i o n a l a d e q u a c y to d e c i d e the q u e s t i o n . We will tion", i.e. little or filtered follow the no specific o ut semantic here by component. A approach. dependent motivation". lation of the preference syntactic rule whose description It is We of rule component, components "modular" of o v e r g e n e r a t i o n , of information, another interaction of rule rule-specific Sag's preference that overproduction in most will particular results is s o m e t i m e s a from form through Sag's h o w e v e r , w i t h d e t e r m i n e d rigor. rule of Gapping information to be whatsoever. the proposed of "in strategy The f o r m u contains Restrictions are no seen to f o l l o w f r o m s e m a n t i c c o n d i t i o n s a l o n g the l i n e s o f Sag, from syntactic chapter conditions 3 below). that To m o t i v a t e are o ur not is the i n d i c a t e d as the promising carry "overgenera schemata with rule-specific formulation of the or (cf. rule, t h r e e a s p e c t s o f p r e v i o u s l y p r o p o s e d f o r m u l a t i o n s of the rule of G a p p i n g w i l l be d i s c u s s e d here: (i) the d o m a i n o f the rule; (ii) the s p e c i f i c a t i o n o f the r e m n a n t s ; (iii) the n u m b e r of gaps. These aspects will be d i s c u s s e d in the and following 3 sections in the o r d e r given. 2.1. O ne T H E D O M A I N O F T H E RULE of the domain of Gapping m a ins, cf. most important is that the observations as regards the rule c a n a p p l y in e m b e d d e d do the f o l l o w i n g e x a m p l e s (Sag 1976, 267): (28) a. Bill said that B e t s y p l a y e d s h o r t s t o p , and Alan isté-'iiû 1st base. B i l l zei dat B e t s y k o r t e s t o p z o u z i j n en A l a n eerste honkman (Bill s a i d that B e t s y s h o r t stop w o u l d be a n d A l a n fi r s t b a s e v M v l W / W . ) - 88 - b. That A l a n p l a y e d 1st b a s e a n d B e t s y p s h o r t s t o p , is n o t s u r p r i s i n g , D at A l a n e e r s t e h o n k m a n w a s en B e t s y k o r t e stop , v e r b a a s t me niets. (That A l a n first b a s e w a s and B e t s y s h o r t stop , su r p r i s e s > m e n o t h i n g . ) Sag (1976) assumes that level of (28), end-variables shallow W4 ) Sa g deletion structure. should s c r i p t i o n o f the rule. and all For be Gapping added Together with introduces rules to apply then the after to the apply structural to de these e nd-variables S-brackets. The rule of (W^ Gapping f o l l o w i n g f r o m this is (29). (29) G a p p i n g (Sag 1976, 278) W 3 - [ 3X 2 - W i - ( X 2 ) * ~ W 2 ] - {and,or} - [gX 2 - W ;L- (X 2 )*- W 2] - W 4 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0 10 9 11=^ 0 11 In this rule, W is a true v a r i a b l e (any n u m b e r o f c o n s t i t u p ents) a nd X a b b r e v i a t e s f o r c o n s t i t u e n t s w i t h t w o bars, thus N 2 (= N P ), P 2 ( = P P ) , A 2 (= A P ), a n d V 2 (=VP) (cf. B r e s n a n 1976 for the f o r m u l a t i o n of r u l e s w i t h v a r i a b l e c o n s t i t u e n t s ) . The s ta r s o v e r t e r m s 4 a nd 9 i n d i c a t e that the t e r m s m a y c o n t a i n 2 a n a r b i t r a r y n u m b e r of X - c o n s t i t u e n t s . S ag d o e s n o t e x p l a i n the i n t r o d u c t i o n of S - b r a c k e t s , but their the effect u se a voi d e d , is of evid e n t . brackets Since in it is generally transformational agreed rules that must be t h e y s h o u l d be c o n s i d e r e d a s u b j e c t of f u r t h e r st u d y r a t h e r t h a n a s o l u t i o n to the prob l e m . Moreover, apply VP to as we l l . more as shown coordinations F or the sophisticated provided. structural projections This can in c h a p t e r 1, o f S, b ut rule to be done by of (S', S, and.VP). the adding d e s c r i p t i o n o f the rule, of V and obs e r v a t i o n a l l y adequate, specification be not only does Gapping to c o o r d i n a t i o n s o f S' where domain should V 1- b r a c k e t s to a be the V 1 a b b r e v i a t e s for It e x c l u d e s the d e r i v a t i o n - 89 - of (30), in w h i c h Gapping applies to a c o o r d i n a t i o n of N P s (cf. c h a p t e r 1, s e c t i o n 2.1.5.). (30) * T h e t h i r d a t t e m p t to b e g i n to w r i t e a n o v e l and the f o u r t h ! t é IMÎi-'él t4>! i i t i t i a play, ... * D e d e r d e p o g i n g om te b e g i n n e n een n o v e l l e te s c h r i j v e n en de v i e r d e e e n t o n e e l s t u k tilii'S h i'tiii'sh , ... (The t h i r d a t t e m p t fo r to b e g i n a n o v e l to w r i t e a n d the f o u r t h é - t t i é t t / t é t / t é / ï i é é i i i a play t é/ y i f t f é , O n the level of e x p l a n a t o r y a d e q u a c y , ti o n is s u s p i c i o u s . to n e g a t i v e ■■■) however, this d e s c r i p The l a n g u a g e l e a r n i n g c h i l d has n o a c c e s s d a t a suc h as (30). Of course, c i f i c a t i o n c a n be c l a i m e d to be innate, the V 1 - d o m a i n s p e X p r e f e r to l e a v e the d o m a i n u n s p e c i f i e d in the e x p e c t a t i o n that r e s t r i c t i o n s on it are to be I will explained by independent constraints. propose In s e c t i o n 3 to d e r i v e s u c h a c o n s t r a i n t f r o m r e s t r i c t i o n s o n L o g i c a l Form. A n o t h e r p o s s i b i l i t y is to d e r i v e it f r o m the syntactic Major Constituent Condition to be discussed in c h a p t e r 3. 2.2. THE REMNANTS The r u l e s o f G a p p i n g p r e s e n t e d by H a n k a m e r a n d S t i l l i n g s e x p r e s s two c h a r a c t e r i s t i c s o f the r e m n a n t s ; restrict the n u m b e r of t h e i r r e mnan t s , of c o n s t i t u e n t s m a y f u n c t i o n as may be number a first remnant. of remnants this restriction (cf. (31)), is The allowed; correct f irst, the r ules and second; all k i n d s second remnants, first restriction the for upper limit English it is n o t in o t h e r s (cf. an d it d oes n o t h o l d in D u t c h at all: (32)) in b ut o n l y N P specifies is two. some the Though instances (Sag 1976, 196-7), - 90 - (31) a. * A l a n gav e S a n d y a book, and Peter ü - f i Betsy a magazine. A l a n g a f S a n d y eert b o e k en P e t e r H f Betsy een tijdschrift. b. * A l a n t o l d H a r r y th a t the s k y w a s f a l l i n g a n d S a m B e t s y that C h i c k e n L i t t l e w a s right. A l a n v e r t e l d e H a r r y dat de l u c h t n a a r b e n e d e n k w a m en S a m - f i f t é t é i B e t s y da t C h i c k e n L i t t l e g e l i j k had. ( A l a n t o l d H a r r y th a t the sky d o w n - b e l o w c a m e a n d S a m jt<t>té B e t s y that C h i c k e n L i t t l e r i g h t w a s .) c. * A r i z o n a e l e c t e d G o l d w a t e r S e n a t o r a nd Massachussetts McCormack Congressman. A r i z o n a k o o s G o l d w a t e r in de s e n a a t en M a s s a c h u s s e t t s yL&ó£ M c C o r m a c k in h e t c o n g r e s . ( A r i z o n a e l e c t e d G o l d w a t e r in the s e n a t e a n d Massachussetts (32) a. 1 M c C o r m a c k in the c o n g r e s s ) Pe^ter t a l k e d to h i s b o s s o n T u e s d a y , and Betsy to h e r s u p e r v i s o r o n W e d n e s d a y . P i e t h e e f t d i n s d a g m e t z i j n b a a s g e s p r o k e n en Betsy w o e nsdag met haar w e r kleider (Piet h a s T u e s d a y to H i s b o s s t a l k e d a n d Betsy W e d n e s d a y to h e r s u p e r v i s o r ' u i n t .) b. J o h n t a l k e d to h i s s u p e r v i s o r a b o u t h i s t h e sis, a n d E r i c h t &t Mi 1 to the d e a n a b o u t d e p a r t m e n t a l politics. John heeft met zijn werkleider over zijn p r o e f s c h r i f t g e s p r o k e n en E r i k Jh é i t t m e t de d e k a a n over instituutszaken • 91 - It s e e m s that remnants are a c c e p t a b l e of the VP. in E n g l i s h g a p p e d s e n t e n c e s w i t h m o r e t h a n two Sag only considers if this the t h i r d r e m n a n t is o u t s i d e restriction unimportant (p. 278) : "Much of A.H.N.] the can overgeneration be ruled out by of a thi s rule surface |i.e. (29), constraint of the s or t i l l u s t r a t e d in (3.4.53) (3.4.53) where V # [s X 2 [V 1 C* stands (VP)). As siderably tences for any sequence previously among like X 2 - C*] ] , speakers. (3.4.54), of c o n s t i t u e n t s mentioned, Th u s judgements som e whose Gapped people (within vary con accept sen r i g h t c o n j u n c t h a s the structure: L N 2 [ . N 2 S 2 ] ] . b yl ( 3.4.54) %Ja n i s t o l d A l a n that he w a s c r a z y , and Betsy P e t e r t h a t he s h o u l d go to tak e a bath. O u r G a p p i n g r u l e g e n e r a t e s such s e n t e n c e s . tal variation surface natural is handled constraints. way by This, to h a n d l e w h a t The i d i o l e c - positing slightly I claim, would different is a very s e e m to be c o m p l e t e l y i d i o s y n c r a t i c d i f f e r e n c e s in a c c e p t a b i l i t y j u d g e m e n t s . " L et us assume that thi s is correct. Then the difference b e t w e e n E n g l i s h a n d D u t c h with, r e s p e c t to the G a p p i n g p h e n o mena the observed (3.4.53) in (31) are reduced to fact tha t filter is p a r t of the g r a m m a r o f E n g l i s h (at l e ast for som e speakers), b u t a b s e n t f r o m the g r a m m a r o f Dutch. Secondly, the rules of Hankamer and Stillings specify the f i r s t r e m n a n t of G a p p i n g as N P . T h i s r e s t r i c t i o n a r b i t r a r il y narrows that the c h o i c e the s c ope of the rule. of the f i r s t r e m n a n t c h o i c e of the s e c o n d r emnant, Sag c f .: (33) a. At our house, we p l a y p o k e r , at B e t s y ' s house, (1976, 265) shows is just as f r e e as the and b r i dge. - 92 - (33) a. (oont.) Bij ons s p e l e n we poker, bij B e t s y en b r i dge . (At o u r ('s) p l a y we po k e r , at B e t s y and ( 1s) i t & H M b r i d g e . ) b. Y e s t e r d a y we v e n t to the m o v i e s , and last T h u r s d a y , iii/itiiif to the c ircus. G i s t e r e n g i n g e n we n a a r de f i l m en vorige week donderdag $4 n a a r h e t ci r c u s . ( Y e s t e r d a y w e n t we to the m o v i e s and last w e e k T h u r s d a y 'fiiis.t fii<i to the c i r c u s . ) O n e ' s c h o i c e o f r e m n a n t s is, h o w e v e r , particular, (34) n o t c o m p l e t e l y free. V 2 m a y not be l e f t b e h i n d (Sag 1976, *0n T u e s d a y , Sa m m ust h ave s e e m e d ha p p y , In 266): and o n W e d n e s d a y , tf.i m u s t h a v e s e e m e d sad. Sa g c o n c l u d e s that the s e c o n d X "must be restricted would presumably be so ? t hat done in h is rule it cannot 2 analyze by means of syntactic V . T his feat u r e s , bu t we w ill no t p u r s u e t h a t m a t t e r h e r e . " It seems, however, t hat features only obscures ing. It cannot be a solution in terms of syntactic a fundamental problem regarding Gapp accidental t hat Gapping always deletes verbs. 2 By s t a t i n g tha t the r e m n a n t s o f G a p p i n g a re X - c o n s t i t u ents, Sag e x c l u d e s s e n t e n c e s suc h as (Sag 1976, (35) 275-6): *Did B e t s y e a t the p e a c h e s or d i d H a r r y the g r a p e s ? Heeft Betsy p e r ziken gegeten of heeft Harrie druiven (36) *Betsy s a i d that A l a n w e n t to the b a l l g a m e a n d that B e t s y itiiit to the m o v ie s . *Be t s y zei dat A l a n n a a r de v o e t b a l w e d s t r i j d g i n g e n dat M a r y n a a r de f i l m i i t é ’ - 93 - In ge n e r a l , o n l y m a j o r p h r a s e s m a y f u n c t i o n as G a p p i n g rem2 nants. O b s e r v e h o w e v e r , t h a t the X - r e s t r i c t i o n on G a p p i n g runs i nto t r o u b l e w i t h s e n t e n c e s such as (37): (37) a. Bil l s a w Harry, ( L a s n i k 1972, not H a r r y Bill. 90) Bill za g Harrie, m a a r H a r r i e 04, B i l l niet. (Bill saw Harry, bu t H a r r y Bill not) b. Bill k o m t wel, e n H a r r i e Ksitfit niet. (Bill c o m e s d e f i n i t e l y , Bill d o e s come, and Harry not; an d H a r r y d o e s n o t c o m e . ) N o t , n i e t a n d wel (the r e v e r s e of n o t , u s u a l l y r e p r e s e n t e d in o E n g l i s h b y a f o r m of "to do") c a n n o t be X - c o n s t i t u e n t s . T h e y form a special Therefore, 2 class, apart f rom the projections of X. the X - r e s t r i c t i o n o n G a p p i n g c a n n o t be m a i n t a i n ed. S a g ' s o b s e r v a t i o n that X 1- c o n s t i t u e n t s c a n n o t be r e m n a n t s of G a p p i n g ho l d s . not that e m e r g i n g g e n e r a l i z a t i o n , h o w e v e r , does ? o n l y X - c o n s t i t u e n t s c a n f u n c t i o n as f o r G a p ping, b u t r a t h e r t hat n o n m a x i m a l i z e d c o n s t i seem to remnants be The t u e n t s m a y n e v e r f u n c t i o n as r e m n a n t . principles of Universal Grammar, s t a t e d in the r u l e of G a p p i n g . T h i s s h o u l d f o l l o w from an d therefore n e e d s n o t be We w i l l r e t u r n to the p r o b l e m o f r e s t r i c t i n g the shape of the r e m n a n t s in c h a p t e r 3. 2.3. In THE G A P S several structural descriptions of Gapping recently p r o p o s e d the n u m b e r o f d e l e t i o n s i t e s is s e v e r e l y r e s t r i c t e d . The rules contain one proposed gap by only, Fiengo (1974) and Stillings those proposed by Hankamer (1975) (1973) a nd Sag (1976) c o n t a i n two: an i n t e r n a l one a n d a r i g h t p e r i p h e r a l one. but Most examples with more nevertheless internal gaps t here (38), are t h a n on e g ap o b e y t h i s pat t e r n , examples or e v e n w i t h with leftperipheral three gaps and (39). T h o u g h the - 94 - latter appear far-fetched, the gapping schema itself is p r o b a b l y no t the p l a c e to e x p r e s s t he s e j u d g e m e n t s . (38) T h e r e h a s b e e n s ome f l o u r a d d e d to the s a u c e b y Peter and /$&$/$$<£$■ some w a t e r t<t/ M i / b y John. E r is m e e l bij de s aus g e d a a n d o o r P i e t en m u water u a u i u M i m & u d o o r Jan. (There is flour to the s a u c e a d d e d b y P i e t a n d m t a u (39) water / M i / 4 Mi 4 / b y Jan.) 'There ha s b een som e f l o u r a d d e d to the s a u c e b y me an d f i f i i f i / W i i * - som e w a t e r ¡¿00#$ to the soup - E r is d o o r P e t e r mee l bij de s a u s g e d a a n en door Jan M i t bij de s o e p (There is b y P e t e r f l o u r to the sauce a d d e d a n d t $ 4 t i f i $ by Jan In Dutch, the distribution tively unrestricted, to the s o u p &.<ji<fri<fr. of adverbial phrases . is c o m p a r a an d c o n s e q u e n t l y e x a m p l e s w i t h m o r e t h a n one i n t e r n a l gap are r e a d i l y a v a i l a b l e : (40) M a r i e h e e f t in de k o f f i e p a u z e e e n a f s p r a a k g e m a a k t me t h a a r v r i e n d i n n e n en K a r e l i i t t in de l u n c h p a u z e met zijn vrienden. (Marie h a s d u r i n g the c o f f e e b r e a k a d a t e m a d e w i t h h e r g i r l f r i e n d s an d K a r e l yi&i d u r i n g l u n c h t i m e with his friends.) In p r i n c i p l e , an infinite number of gaps is possible. T his n u m b e r is p r e s u m a b l y r e s t r i c t e d o n l y b y the f i x e d c a p a c i t y of human working memory, and stylistic traditions. It s u g g e s t s t hat one s h o u l d no t a i m to s p e c i f y the n u m b e r or the p l a c e of the g a p s in the rule of G a p p i n g itself. - OS 2.4. C O N S E Q U E N C E S F O R TH E F O R M U L A T I O N OF G A P P I N G A rule of discussed will Gapping which h a v e a sim p l e the one p r o p o s e d covers all structural examples hitherto description, s u c h as in c h a p t e r 1 (un d e r (84), r e p e a t e d h e r e f or c o n v e n i e n c e ): (41) G a p p i n g A ¥1 1 This W2 2 3 ion between 5 =7* makes no 0 specific 2 0 claims 4 0 about the domain, o r the g a p s o f the rule, e x c e p t f o r a d i s t i n c t "t r u e " v a r i a b l e s (A a n d B) . The of W3 4 formulation the r e m n a n t s , B remnants r ule (no (W) and "constituent" variables is r e s t r i c t e d w i t h r e s p e c t to the n u m b e r m ore than two) and the number of gaps (no m o r e t h a n three). A f o r m u l a w h i c h d r o p s t h i s s p e c i f i c a t i o n as w e l l w o u l d be: (42) G a p p i n g (final v e r s i o n ) "D e l e t e " The rule is s i m i l a r to C h o m s k y ' s "Move <*. " for m o v e m e n t r u l e s 1978, as (C h o m s k y between follow tru e 4). Fo r Gapping variables axiomatically, an d in in (42) constituent the same way the difference variables as the should axiom for m o v e m e n t r u l e s p r e d i c t s that o n l y c o n s t i t u e n t s c a n be moved. Of solved course, by grammatical hand, ings the one gapped as rule well. constraints t his formula in can "Del e t e " : it g e n e r a t e s it (42) of v i e w that derives the problem trivially be g e n e r a t e d . on v a r i a b l e s , perspective learnability point all-and-only as Consequently is Gapping the does not generate trivially, motivated from of Gapping sentences proposed exclusively: gappings half formulating O n the o t h e r grammatical all independently a n d d omain. the somewhat its significance. rul e gapp- ungrammatical requires remnants is all It impecunious From is q u i t e a t t r a c t i v e : a the - 96 - child only displays needs (42), a point of m e t h o d rule-specific ward to that the ripheral NP relevance, su c h for or not the language c o n t e x t it h o l d s as s h o u l d n o t be c l u t t e r e d up w i t h as devices. t h os e Condition, Straightfor assembled by S ag by Hankamer under the Lef t a n d by L a n g e n d o e n u n d e r the N o n L e f t - p e Condition, and, whether the p r e s e n t or n o t a t i o n a l No-Ambiguity Peripheral Deletion, in (42) conditions counterexamples under learn Therefore, have tha t in fac t reason, only should little lea v e systematic one u n w i l l i n g to giv e up the u n a d o r n e d v e r s i o n o f (42), Even then, formulating "Coindex". G ap p i n g . some c o m m e n t s are Gapping The as choice "Delete", relates G a p p i n g is c l a i m e d in o r d e r on a n d n o t as to o ur the c h o i c e of "Interpret", or modular approach r e l a t i n g the a n t e c e d i n g s t r i n g a n d the g a p p e d stri n g , other restricting the of to be g o v e r n e d by two rules: one extent of the gap. The a n d the difference b e t w e e n these two r u l e s is d i s p l a y e d b y the a r r o w s in (43). As argued above ( c h a p t e r 1, s e c t i o n 2 . 1 . 7 . ) the the gapped part of and sentence anteceding grammar. string More wil l r e l a t i o n in s e c t i o n 3 of t h i s c h a p t e r . relating gap, the r e m n ants, a n d thus as chapter 3, where to constrained be formulating (42), this rule and movement a l ike. It is no r u les commonly s e nse insofar referred as it said about be thi s the rule of G a p p i n g is discussed in rules will obvious shows considered the e x t e n t of the This part a n d its p r o p e r t i e s will this p a r t of G a p p i n g as makes be be In c o n t r a s t , specifying is a r ul e of s e n t e n c e g r a m m a r . formalized the rule r e l a t i n g cannot from be s h o w n (43) that "Coindex" or "Interpret" no resemblance to the to as r u l e s o f c o i n d e x i n g or i n t e r - 97 - pretation. One m a y further speculate deletes terminal elements, stamps" to strings content (by a n o p t i o n a l to roe t h a t this about whether (42) actually or w h e t h e r it just g i v e s " a p p r o v a l of c o n s t i t u e n t s w h i c h received no lexical rule of lexical insertion). It s e e m s d i s t i n c t i o n c a n n o t be s h o w n to be m e a n i n g f u l at p r e s e n t . 3. R E C O V E R A B I L I T Y Lees (1960, two s t r i n g s the 75) observes that is an i n s u f f i c i e n t underscored constituents phonological identity of condition for recoverability: in (44) do n o t c o u n t as ident ical, as (45) shows. (44) are h a r d to r e s cue. Drowning_cats D r o w n i n g c a t s is a g a i n s t the law. (45) ^ D r o w n i n g cats, ' w h i c h is a g a i n s t the law, are h a r d to rescue. He that concludes constituents Ross of p h r a s e ab i l i t y . in a nd "it is n e c e s s a r y to specify that the two q u e s t i o n h a v e the sa m e p h r a s e s t r u c t u r e . " Lakoff (Lakoff 1968, 54) showed that identity s t r u c t u r e is an i n s u f f i c i e n t c o n d i t i o n f o r r e c o v e r They present arguments th a t d e e p and d e r i v e d s t r u c t u r e is r e l e v a n t . information from both The 'argument that the level o f d e e p s t r u c t u r e is i n v o l v e d in r e c o v e r a b i l i t y runs as foll o w s . C o n s i d e r (46): (46) T he c h i c k e n s are r e a d y to eat. This sentence that the c h i c k e n s are g o i n g to eat is two-way ambiguous, g o i n g to be eaten. S i m ilarly, two-way ambiguous, nation. resulting since or t h a t in (47), it means the c h i c k e n s are either the c o n j u n c t s e a c h are in a f o u r - w a y a m b i g u o u s c o o r d i - 98 - (47) The c h i c k e n s are rea d y to eat a n d the c h i l d r e n are r e a d y to eat. Application (47), of however, VP-deletion reduces the in the number structure of available underlying interpreta- tians to two as in (48). (48) The c h i c k e n s are rea d y to eat a n d the c h i l d r e n are 0, too. T h i s m e a n s e i t h e r t h a t b o t h the c h i c k e n s and the c h i l d r e n are going to eat structure whether or that position or not both of are going chickens and to be eaten. children The deep thus determines the V P s i n v o l v e d a r e i d e n t i c a l , i.e. recover able . On the o t h e r hand, it is c l e a r that the V P s in (48) are not i d e n t i c a l at the level o f d e e p s t r u c t u r e : a subject or object c h i l d r e n , and the o n e c o n t a i n s as other contains as a s u b j e c t or o b j e c t c h i c k e n s , cf. b. P R O e a t s b. P R O e a t s the c h i c k e n s the c h i l d r e n T h i s d i s s i m i l a r i t y d o e s not d i s a p p e a r e a r l i e r t h a n in d e r i v e d structure. Within do no the Lakoff could appear in the d e r i v e d standard more than theory claim that of Chomsky "items s t r u c t u r e a r e c o m p l e t e l y i r r e l e v a n t to the q u e s t i o n o f l i n g u i s t i c a l l y s i g n i f i c a n t i d e n t i t y . " 1968, 65). (1965), t h a t do n o t (Lakoff - 99 - After the F i e n g o 1974, of the introduction problem had been offer a representation are united of an d C h o m s k y 1976), in a the tra c e standard in w h i c h natural theory (Chomsky 1973, it b e c a m e c l e a r t h a t the core way. theory's inability to deep and surface information The introduction of traces c l e a r s the w a y f or f o u r d i f f e r e n t s h a l l o w s t r u c t u r e s o f (47). At this level, the c o n j u n c t s o f (47) receive two structures each : (50) F i r s t c o n j u n c t of ( 4 7 ) : a. The c h i c k e n s a r e r e a d y (e )Np to eat. i b. The c h i c k e n s ^ are r e a d y (e )Np to eat . (e )Np . i Second conjunct of ( 4 7 ) : a. The c h i l d r e n , are rea d y (e).m 1 b. involved, ment (e)M _ to eat ,] temporarily the (e)M _ . INF . j INF different indices of the NPs these s t r u c t u r e s a l l o w for a s t r a i g h t f o r w a r d s t a t e of (50a) J The c h i l d r e n , are r e a d y Disregarding to eat. Nr . recoverability: (ready (e )Np to the representations eat) an d (50b) of (rea d y the VPs (e )^p to in eat (e )N P ) are not i d e n t i c a l , a n d t h e r e f o r e the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n of (48) in w h i c h the c h i l d r e n are g o i n g to eat a n d the c h i c k e n s are going level of explain to be shallow the eaten (or v i c e structure thus recoverability of versa) se e m s does to be VP-deletion not exist. The r i c h e n o u g h to as regards the s t r u c t u r e u n d e r l y i n g (47). Sag (1976, t han the level establish m ent 121) shows that a of s h a l l o w s t r u c t u r e more sophisticated level is n e c e s s a r y in o r d e r to linguistically significant redundancy. Sag's argu is b a s e d o n an i n t r i g u i n g v a r i a n t of the " r e a d y to eat" examples. (51) T he c h i c k e n s are r e a d y to eat, a r e r e a d y to 0, also. a n d the c h i l d r e n - 100 - Unlike ively are (48), for t his that sentence reading going to eat. appearence of the and chickens are is u n a m b i g u o u s . in w h i c h There is second going both no way to interpretation to be It a l l o w s e x c l u s chickens eaten) and explain (both if d e f i n e d at the l evel o f s h a l l o w s t r u c t u r e , children the the dis- children recoverability cf. is (52): (52) The c h i c k e n s ^ are r e a d y (e)Np to eat (e)Np a. the c h i l d r e n , are r e a d y (e )jjp to eat and i (e )N p . b. the c h i l d r e n , are r e a d y (e ) ^ p to eat J (e )^p . j If the u n d e r s c o r e d s t r i n g in (52a) is r e c o v e r a b l e , it s h o u l d f o l l o w t hat the u n d e r s c o r e d s t r i n g in (52b) is r e c o v e r a b l e as well. The level is c l e a r l y not of shallow the level structure (incorporating at w h i c h the a m b i g u i t y of the u n a m b i g u i t y of (51) ca n be e x p l a i n e d . Sag (p. 98) traces) (48) vs. ’ solves t his p r o b l e m by r e f e r r i n g to a n o t h e r l evel of r e p r e s e n t a t i o n : the level of L o g i c a l F o r m ( i n t r o d u c ed by C h o m s k y 1975, 105). At this level all s h a l l o w s t r u c t u r es are t r a n s f o r m e d int o l a m b d a - e x p r e s s i o n s , s u c h as (53). (53) B e t s y , X x (x l o v e s Peter) "Betsy loves Peter" A logical f o r m of this ject-predicate ing-Peter "Betsy type relation to Betsy in loves Peter and by is i n t e n d e d assigning (53). to c a p t u r e the Similarly, Susan loves the sub- of lov- property the Peter" coordination receives the f o l l o w i n g l o g i c a l form: (54) B e t s y , X x (x l o v e s Pet e r ) & Susan, X y (y l o v e s P eter) Linguistic recoverability so-called alphabetic containing variables is now var i a n c e . in defined Two corresponding by the notion expressions A positions, but and of B ident - 101 - ical otherwise, variables all variables that are in A to bound be alphabetic in A is at recoverable the l e vel of variants, in p r e c i s e l y in B are b o u n d in B, deletion expression said are if the if Sag's hypothesis the Logical string Form then is is an deleted and all sam e w a y as an alphabetic v a r i a n t of a n o t h e r e x p r e s s i o n at thi s level. In the phabetic lo g i c a l form variance (54), obtains the f o l l o w i n g p a t t e r n o f a l ("=" means "is an alphabetic v a r i a n t of"): (54') a. (x l o ves P e t e r ) < £ (y l o v e s Peter) b, X x (x l o v e s P e t e r ) = X y (y l o v e s P e t e r ) c. B e t s y , X x (x l o v e s P e ter ) ji -Susan, X y (y l o v e s Peter) In (a), but the v a r i a b l e s x a n d y are in c o r r e s p o n d i n g p o s i t i o n s , they differ, pressions, In and (b), are b o u n d w i t h i n they are not bound x a n d y aga i n di f f e r , the within but the this time they e x p r e s s i o n s b y the l a m b d a - o p e r a t o r . The e x p r e s s i o n s in (b) t h e r e f o r e a r e a l p h a b e t i c v a r i a n t s . Betsy differs invariant in fr o m the Susan, which f i r s t place. alphabetic variants variables, and ex if these th e y renders In brie f , differ variables are the In (c), expressions two e x p r e s s i o n s only bound with in respect the same are to way w i t h i n the e x p r e s s i o n s . This procedure allows Sag to explain the mysterious " r eady to eat" e x a m p l e s as foll o w s . On e i n t e r p r e t a t i o n o f the ambiguous (47) ( r e p e a t e d h e r e as (55)), is r e p r e s e n t e d at the level of L o g i c a l F o r m as (55'): (55) The c h i c k e n s are r e a d y to eat a n d the c h i l d r e n are r e a d y to eat. ( 5 5 1) The c h i c k e n s , X x (x r e a d y the c h i l d r e n , X w According to these alphabetic variants, (x , X y (y e a t ) ) ) & (w r e a d y ( w , X z (z e a t ) ) ) logical f o r m s ,X y (...) and X z as are X x (...) a n d X w (,..). (...) are Thus, b o t h - 102 - s m a l l a n d lar g e V P - d e l e t i o n is r e c o v e r a b l e , a n d (48), In r e s u l t i n g in (51) respectively. the second interpretation, (55") at the level o f L o g i c a l F o r m (55) is represented as (emp t y s u b j e c t s are r e p r e s e n t e d as du m m i e s ) . (55") The c h i c k e n s ,, X x (x r e a d y ( a , X y (y e a t x) )) & the ch i l d r e n , X w (w re a d y (a, X z ( z e a t w ) )) In this logical variants, (...), form, X x but X z since x (...) a nd w (...) is are not a nd X w an bound outside L a r g e V P - d e l e t i o n is r e c o v e r a b l e , not. (...) are alphabetic while the s e small alphabetic variant of A y expressions. V P - d e l e t i o n is T h i s e x p l a i n s w h y (51) c a n n o t r e c e i v e the i n t e r p r e t a t i o n that the c h i c k e n s and the c h i l d r e n are g o i n g to be eaten, and thus the u n a m b i g u i t y of (51) vs. the a m b i g u i t y of (48). This presents is deletion is stru c t u r e . only pairs fi r s t not to Further ph e n o m e n a , not the (and very strong) in s u p p o r t of h i s h y p o t h e s i s be arguments at the involve w h i c h i n t e r a c t w i t h de l e t i o n . in V P - d e l e t i o n , as defined w e l l . We will phenomenon with Gapping but argument Sag that r e c o v e r a b i l i t y of level quantifier of shallow and fo c u s T h i s c a n be o b s e r v e d in G a p p i n g a n d Q u e s t i o n - A n s w e r illustrate Sag's analysis a nd Q u e s t i o n - A n s w e r p a i r s , of this s i n c e the d e l e t i o n p a t t e r n s c an be r e p r o d u c e d in Dut c h . Consider in this respect the following 1976, 285). (56) Q: W h o d o e s B e t s y love? a. A: B e t s y l o v e s Péter. b . A : *Bétsy l o v e s Peter. Q : Van wie houdt Betsy? (Of w h o m l o v e s Be t s y ? ) a. A: B e t s y h o u d t v a n Péter. & b . A : B é tsy h o u d t v a n P e t e r . (B e t s y lov e s of Pe t e r . ) discourses (Sag - 103 - The ungrammaticality of (56b) shows that the stress pattern of an a n s w e r is d i c t a t e d b y the q u e s t i o n asked. that stressed or focussed elements l evel of L o g i c a l F o r m as in (57) (57) The Q: W h o - x b. A: { B e t s y i } c £ (i, X w logical Peter {*a } c a (Betsy, X y { P e t e r o } c 6 (Betsy, X z who at the (y l o v e s a)) (z l o v e s o)) (w l o v e s P e t e r ) ) f o r m of the q u e s t i o n in (57) r e p r e s e n t s the fact is one of of the form is Let us a s s u m e represented (cf. C h o m s k y 1976, 3 3 ) : ^ a. A: logical that are one of the set of answer the set people (57a) of loved by represents people loved Betsy. the by The fact B etsy. that (57b) r e f l e c t s the m e a n i n g tha t B e t s y is one o f ’the p e o p l e w h o love P eter. By the assumption that well-formed Question-Answer p a i r s share a l p h a b e t i c v a r i a n t s at the level of L o g i c a l Form, the ill-formedness of ed: the since Furthermore, and a( . . . ) in (57) an d a ( ...) hypothesis are alphabetic regarding not thus m a y take a n e l l i p t i c a l form, variants. recoverability d e l e t i o n p r e d i c t s that o (...) is r e d u n d a n t h e r e b y . in (56a) are (56a) o n the o t h e r h a n d is a w e l l - f o r m e d o (...) Sag's as an a n s w e r to (56) is p r e d i c t i (...) , alphabetic variants. answer, (56b) expressions of The a n s w e r cf: (56') Q: W h o d oes B e t s y love? A: Péter. Q: V a n wi e h o u d t B e t s y ? (Of w h o m loves B e t s y ? ) A: V a n Peter, (Of P e t e r . ) Fo r lowed multiple (Sag 1976, WH-questions, multiple 286), connecting abstraction the l o g i c a l to the Q u e s t i o n - A n s w e r p a i r s in (58). forms is in al (59) - 104 - (58) Q: W h o gave the b o o k to w h o m ? A: B é t s y gave the b o o k to Péter. Q: W i e g a f h e t b o e k a a n w i e ? A: B é t s y ga f h e t b o e k a a n Péter. (59) Q : W h o-x, w h o - y , {x& , y u } c a u (a, X z (z gave the b o o k to u)) A: {fletsy^, P e t e r Q } ,c 1 6 (i, X w (w g a v e the b o o k too)) (58) is (the underscored well-formed, since the expressions in corresponding (59)) are logical forms alphabetic vari ants . S a g u s e s t h i s type of s e t - a b s t r a c t i o n f o r the r e p r e s e n t ation of the particular t i o n - A n s w e r pairs, is substantiated gapped sentences accent patterns not only but In g a p p e d s e n t e n c e s as well. by the depends fact that on a c c e n t the in Qu e s - This move well-formedness of as m u c h as the w e l l - f o r m e d n e s s of Q u e s t i o n - A n s w e r p a i r s does. C o n s i d e r : (60) J o h n k i s s e d S u s a n in the k i t c h e n a n d P é t e r Mary • J o h n k u s t e S u s a n in de k e u k e n en P é t e r KyMW (61) Marie ■ * J 6 h n k i s s e d S u s a n in the k i t c h e n a n d M a r y In the d i n i n g room. *Jan k u s t e S u s a n in de k é u k e n en M a r i e in de é é t k am e r . At the level of Logical Form, (60) and (61) are represented as foll o w s : (60') IJ o h n , S u s a n J c a u (a, X x (x k i s s u in the 1 a’ u > ----- 1— !----- 1------------------kitchen) ) & (Peter.^, M a r y Q } c (y k i s s o in the k i t c h e n ) ) I 6 (i , X y - 105 - (61') I1J o h n cl , k i t c h e n U 5 I c a Û (a. A x (x— k i.... s s -S u s a n in u) ..) & {Mary^ , d i n i n g r o o m } c î 6 (John, A y (y k i s s i ino)) The u n d e r s c o r e d e x p r e s s i o n s in (60') are a l p h a b e t i c v a r i a n t s , but the u n d e r s c o r e d e x p r e s s i o n s (60) is w e l l - f o r m e d , As provide Sag points entities ability) but out, the of which be variance. straction, it is p o s s i b l e deletion the same m e a n s s am e l e vel As the the are not. forms (an d thu s established Given in (61') logical (un)identity can alphabetic deletion, in Therefore, (61) is not. the jus t the through (ir)recover the lambda-notation to d e f i n e presented notion and of set-ab the r e c o v e r a b i l i t y of VP Question-Answer pairs, and Gapping by (the n o t i o n o f a l p h a b e t i c v a r i a n c e ) a n d at the (the l e vel of L o g i c a l Form). regards following the analysis conclusions. of G a p p i n g , the a b o v e Set-abstraction of suggests constituents w h i c h c a n be q u e s t i o n e d or a n s w e r e d s u g g e s t s t h a t t h e s e c o n stituents are also possible remnants of Gapping, r e m n a n t s o f G a p p i n g are s e t - a b s t r a c t e d as w e l l . ly, the d oe s verb, not which undergo is n o t a possible WH-movement, and remnant cannot be since the Interesting of Gappi n g , a possible an swer: (62) *Jóhn k i s s e d B e t s y a n d P é t e r h i t . J â n z ó é n d e B e t s y en P e t e r s l ô ê g , (63) Q: A: W h a t d i d J o h n do? *Kissed. Q: A: Given W a t d e e d Jan? *Zóénde. set-abstraction explanation same: verbs logical form of do the for both rules, u n g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of not set-abstract, and for the g a p p e d s e n t e n c e s A n s w e r p a i r s in (63). it must be that the (62) and (63) is the the r e is thu s no apt (62) a n d the Q u e s t i o n - - 106 - Furthermore, where quantifiers Form: the there are, are beginning instance, the phrasable either t wo of S meanings as according represented "the r e a nd of to Sag, at the the two p o s i t i o n s level of beginning "Some o n e of Logical VP. hit everyone" For (para- is one p e r s o n w h o h i t e v e r y o n e " , or "for all p e o p l e the r e is someone, n o t n e c e s s a r i l y the same p erson, w h o h it him " ) are r e p r e s e n t e d as (Sag 1976, 107): (64) a. Ex (x, Ay (Az (y h i t z ))) b. Az (Ex (x, X y (y h i t z ))) If we assume straction as that well, these p o s i t i o n s it f o l l o w s that are a v a i l a b l e the d o m a i n s recoverability of Gapping and no the u n d e r s c o r e d e x p r e s s i o n s other, can be v e r i f i e d are in for s e t - a b at w h i c h the S', S and V P , (65), (66) and (67) b e i n g a l p h a b e t i c v a r i a n t s . (65) S ' : . W h o - x |x . apples U ‘ 1 c —a--------------------------------u (a, A w (w ate u)) & 'el w h o - y jyi , p e a r s Q } c i o (i, Az (z ate o)) (66) S: {J o h n a , a p p l e s u } c a G (a, Ax (x ate u)) & { P e t e r j , p e a r s „ ) c I 6 (i, A y (y ate o)) (67) VP; John, A x ({a p p l e & , M a r y ^ ) c a u (x g a v e a to u)) & ({p e a r i , Sue„ | c l 6 (x g a v e i to o)) In fact, t h i s p r e d i c t i o n is b o r n e out by the g a p p e d s e n t e n c e s below. ( 6 5 ’) S ’: W h o a te a p p l e s a n d w h o pears? W i e at a p p e l s en w i e &f. p e r e n ? (66') S: ■ J o h n ate a p p l e s a nd P e t e r J a n at a p p e l s en P e t e r pears. peren. - 107 - (67') VP: J o h n g ave an a p p l e to M a r y a nd ¿fof# a p e a r to Sue. J a n g a f e e n a p p e l aa n M a r i e en ¿¿.f e e n p e e r aan Susan. Both an d the the observation fact that it that applies Gapping in always deletes verbs certain domains now follow from the d e f i n i t i o n o f r e c o v e r a b i l i t y . For the f o r m u l a t i o n o f the rule o f G a p p i n g t his a c c o u n t e n t a i l s that the d o m a i n s o f the r ule n e e d n o t be s p e c i f i c a l l y pr o v i d e d , wil l and always fully, that belong assuming there to Sag's the is n o need deleted notion of to specify parts. t hat Even recoverability more it verbs force would be t h e o r e t i c a l l y u n d e s i r a b l e to h ave the r ule of G a p p i n g s p e c i f y its d o m a i n or the v e r b as a de l e t e e , g r a n t e d the m a x i m that a rule o n l y s t a t e s w h a t the t h e o r y c a n n o t e x p l a i n . F O O T N O T E S TO C H A P T E R 2 1. A m o r e d i f f i c u l t c a s e is (i), w h i c h is n o t e x c l u d e d by the d e f i n i t i o n of c o n s t i t u e n t v a r i a b l e s ; (i) *John ate at h o m e a n d P e t e r It s e e m s that semantic rather at noon. t h a n s y n t a c t i c d e s p a r i t y is i n v o l v e d here, 2. M y representation of questions minor r e spect. I assume r e p r e s e n t e d as q u a n t i f i e r s , tuents as well. representation that of deviates but as This produces (57). An Question-Answer alphabetic variants, f r o m S a g ' s in one that W H - constituents pairs are n o t only set-abstracted consti the advantage somewhat abundant of t h i s a c c o u n t n o w c a n be s a i d to s h a r e a n d no t o n l y (as S ag does) is, true alphabetic - 108 - variants of possible to (cf. r ul e s 56'), open sentences. present and an allows Th i s elliptical the explains answer statement that that to it is a question all deletion are g o v e r n e d by a r e c o v e r a b i l i t y c o n d i t i o n in ter m s of full a l p h a b e t i c varia n c e . C H A P T E R 3. Constraints In this straints on chapter the we rule will investigate of G a p p i n g as a number formulated of con in c h a p t e r 2 a n d r e p e a t e d h e r e for c o n v e n i e n c e : (1) G a p p i n g Delete In two separate on (i) the p a r t s we will r e m n a n t s o f the be concerned with rule, and (ii) the constraints deleted parts of the rule. In p a r t 1 we w i l l d i s c u s s a n u m b e r of c o n s t r a i n t s o n the contents of the remnants recently proposed Hankamer (1974), C h o m s k y (1976) f i n d that H a n k a m e r ' s M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t C o n d i tion We w i l l is an strictive adequate, means of and, (1973), B r e s n a n by (1973), F i e n g o more constraining (1976) a n d Sag importantly, the the remnants of number of most the re rule of Gapping. In part proposed by 2 we Ross will Lasnik (1977), Chomsky (1978). We will show arity recent between the rule fail the Strict way. Bach of to while Horn (1976), Koster (1978b) out and and and Zwarts W H - m o v e m e n t , these this parallelism is p u t f o r w a r d Constraint constraints Chomsky th e r e e x i s t s a c l e a r s i m i l Gapping bring A n ew p r o p o s a l Subjacency a and (1978), that, constraints revealing discuss (1967), in in a the f o r m . o f in o r d e r to i n c o r p o r a t e the G a p p i n g p h e n o m e n a in a n a d e q u a t e a c c o u n t of s e n t e n c e gramm a r . - 110 - 1. C O N S T R A I N I N G T HE R E M N A N T S 1,1. M A J O R C O N S T I T U E N C Y In H a n k a m e r (1973), the author adds as a condition to the rule of G a p p i n g that the r e m n a n t s be m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s : (2) T he M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t C o n d i t i o n T he r e m n a n t s of G a p p i n g are M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t s , w h e r e m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s are d e f i n e d as f o l lows: (3) M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t s A " m ajor - constituent" constituent either immediately dominated of a given immediately by VP, which d o m i n a t e d by S q . ( H a n k a m e r 1973, To give a n example, stituents, Hankamer to (1971, calization, (5) a G apping, is Sq a or immediately 18 fn.2) circled nodes of (4) are major con the n o t i o n o f " M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t " is c l a i m e d by Hankamer (5) is SQ by and the n o n c i r c l e d n o d e s are not; A s it s hould, Thus, the sentence dominated be relevant to other syntactic rules as well. 79), f or instance, m e n t i o n s the r u l e of T o p i - b y w h i c h o n l y m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s c a n be pr e p o s e d . and (6) nonmajor while Topicalization: are u n g r a m m a t i c a l constituent in (6) f o r the functions as a nonmajor constituent s a m e reason: a remnant in for is p r e p o s e d by ill (5) J o h n s a w the q u e e n of E n g l a n d a n d P e t e r of Hol l a n d . J o h n h e e f t de k o n i n g i n v a n E n g e l a n d g e z i e n en P e t e r / Mt ï i l éi é- v a n N e d e r l a n d (6) O f H o l l a n d P e t e r s a w the queen. ft. V a n N e d e r l a n d h e e f t P e t e r de k o n i n g i n g e z ien. In fact, the Hankamer Major Constituent as a c o n s t r a i n t Condition is suggested by on the a p p l i c a t i o n of all s y n t a c t i c rules. H a n k a m e r (1971 a n d 1973) d o e s n o t d i s t i n g u i s h b e t w e e n S' and S, but daughters preposed ing, if of this S' distinction wi l l be WH-constituent forms a introduced, constituents successful immediate as well: remnant a of Gapp cf.: (7) W h o ate a p p l e s a n d w h o pears? W i e at a p p e l s en w i e Observe not is major furthermore equivalent to that the • peren? the notion notion "major constituent" are c l a u s e m a t e s if t h e y b e l o n g to the sam e s e n t e n t i a l Thus, in (8), s t r u c t u r e d as in are m a j o r c o n s t i t u e n t s , is " c l a u s e m a t e " : t wo c o n s t i t u e n t s (9), the remnants of Gapping b u t not c l a u s e m a t e s : (8) J o h n t r i e d to c l i m b M o n t Blan c , t t U & l t i > l M o u n t E verest. (9) tried VP domain. and Peter - 112 - The Gapping-cum-Major Constituent Condition-analysis m u s t be a u g m e n t e d w i t h a r u l e of N- a n d Ad j - D e l e t i o n . W i t h o u t s u c h a r u l e the s e n t e n c e s in (10) w o u l d be c o u n t e r e x a m p l e s to the Major genitive Constituent NP Condition is i m p o s s i b l e (2). in Dutch, (N-Deletion after a cf. the u n g r a m m a t i c a l i t y of (1 0 a ) .) (10) a. J o h n to o k B i l l ' s c l o t h e s a nd H a r r y J o h n ' s 4t<Î>tïk4é • * J o h n n a m B i l l s k l e r e n en H a r r y Johns b. S. J o h n b o u g h t t h ree b o o k s a nd P e t e r fo u r yséiM- - J o h n k o c h t d r i e b o e k e n en P e t e r Méat vier c. . The f i r s t h o u s e is 50 f e e t d e e p a n d the s e c o n d house 60 fe e t . ' H e t ene h u i s is 5 m e t e r d i e p en h e t a n d e r e h u i s 6 meter The sentences motivated: in even (11) in the ■ show that absence th i s of a rule is independently linguistic antecedent a d j e c t i v e a n d n o u n d e l e t e in su c h s e n t e n c e s : (11) a. H a r r y t o o k J o h n ' s ¡j.lét'Ûi't,. Harry nam Johns b. P e t e r b o u g h t f o u r tyééM • Peter kocht er vier c. The s e c o n d h o u s e is 60 feet H et a n d e r e h u i s is 6 m e t e r Under this plication assumption, of we are a b l e to m a i n t a i n the rul e of G a p p i n g C o n s t i t u e n t Co n d i t i o n . . that the a p is r e s t r i c t e d by the M a j o r - 113 - Several conditions been proposed will now r e v i e w these, as with the predictions other than major c o n s t r a i n t s o n the and compare made by constituency remnants have of Gapping. We the e m p i r i c a l p r e d i c t i o n s the Major Constituent Condi tion. 1 1.2. F I E N G O ' S H E A D C O N D I T I O N R E F O R M U L A T E D AS A M A X I M I Z A T I O N P R I N C I P L E Though Condition presented as Fiengo (1974, of a r e s t r i c t i o n on the gap, the shape of the re m n a n t s , For this reason, 115) at the same time the H e a d influences an d does so in a n I n t e r e s t i n g way. it is u s e f u l to r e v i e w this cond i t i o n here r a t h e r t h a n in the s e c o n d p a r t of th i s c h a p t e r . The concept daughter of daughters a "head" is defined constituent are n o n h e a d s M is as the follows: head only (+m), one all other ( - m ) . W h i c h d a u g h t e r will be the h e a d f o l l o w s f r o m X - b a r theory: V is + m of VP, N is + m of NP, P is +m of, PP, S is +m headless category: Fiengo the formulates interpretation question of of S' , etc. Fiengo of the Head syntactic C o n d i t i o n as structure. of w h e t h e r G a p p i n g is a r u l e interpretation, claims that S is a all d a u g h t e r s o f S w i l l be M. let us refer with a c o n d i t i o n on Disregarding the of d e l e t i o n o r a rule the notion ’ gap' to e i t h e r the d e l e t e e or the i n t e r p r e t e e . (12) H e a d C o n d i t i o n If the g a p c o n t a i n s -m of M, it c o n t a i n s + m o f M. By the below in Head (cf. (13), Condition, Fiengo 1974, the d i s t r i b u t i o n o f 113, 114) (13) v e r s u s (14) is a c c o u n t e d for. A s sh o w n + m c o n s t i t u e n t s m a y be g a p p e d ohne we i t é r é s , a n d -m c o n s t i t u e n t s m a y be g a p p e d if t h e i r h e a d s are g a p p e d as well. (14) is r u l e d out, si n c e a -m c o n s t i t u e n t cannot' d e l e t e if its h e a d (V) d o e s not. (the o b j e c t of VP) - 114 - (13) a. P h i l o s o p h e r s loa t h e b i b l i o m a n c y and mystics reading. F i l o s o f e n h a t e n b i b l i o f o b e n en m y s t i c i bibliofielen. b. He s o l d the A m a t i to S h e r l o c k y e s t e r d a y a n d to M y c r o f t the d a y b efore. u / u u / m / M m Hij v e r k o c h t de S u n b e a m g i s t e r e n a a n K e e s en )hii ! (14) M! ! v a n d a a g a a n Fre d d i e . P h i l o s o p h e r s loathe b i b l i o m a n c y and mystics prefer lifWi i é M Ü • *Fi l o s o f e n h a t e n b i b l i o f o b e n en mystici prefereren As as a well shown are (12), on the Fiengo gap, formulates but it the H e a d C o n d i t i o n could have + m of M, it c o n t a i n s of M m a y n o t remnants as f u n c t i o n as a r e m n a n t u n l e s s w ell. Given c a t e g o r y of. -m (15) c a n f u n c t i o n as are X-bar th e o r y , in condition projections of a -m daughters as w ell, t hat this r e s p e c t is, if X 1 is a f u n c t i o n as a r e m n a n t u n l e s s the 2 of X are r e m n a n t s as well. It f o l l o w s that the o nly p o s s i b l e r e m n a n t in (15) that all n o n h e a d s t his a r e m n a n t o n l y if the a c c o m p a n y i n g remnants X 1 in turn c a n n o t accompanying if a r e m n a n t (15): c constituents remnant, equally -m of M. T h i s i m p l i e s that the prohibits Gapping from producing nonmaximal X in been f o r m u l a t e d as a c o n d i t i o n o n the r e m n a n t s : contains head in condition the H e a d C o n d i t i o n o is X . O b s e r v e is s i m i l a r to w h i c h l o o k s like a v e r s i o n o f the A o v e r A P r i n c i p l e : (16), - 115 - (16) M a x i m i z a t i o n P r i n c i p l e A t r a n s f o r m a t i o n m a y not a p p l y to X n if X n is rn i m m e d i a t e l y d o m i n a t e d b y X , a n d m ~t/ n. The Maximization Principle Principle (Cho m s k y 1973, differs 235) from in two Chomsky's A-over-A essential respects. First, o l d - f a s h i o n e d A - o v e r - A is n o t r e s t r i c t e d to i m m e d i a t e ly dominating e.g. nodes, 2 the c i r c l e d N a n d thus m a y p r o h i b i t in s t r u c t u r e (17) book The i n t e r v e n i n g d e t e r m i n e r n o d e and former s e l e c t i o n of N2 J o h n 's tion the (17). the does projection nonheads. Maximization not of apply, The Principle because a lexical renders the category, both (16) the H e a d C o n d i inapplicable. determiner, not The being a cannot dominate heads and latter does not apply , b e c a u s e the d e t e r m i n e r 2 T h e r e f o r e , the u p p e r N d o e s n o t i m m e d i a t e l y 2 the c i r c l e d N . Second, the A - o v e r - A p r i n c i p l e d o e s node i n t e r v e n e s . dominate not disregard prohibits the the number selection of bar s , of a node and therefore dominated by never a n o t h e r node of the s a m e p r o j e c t i o n type w i t h mor e bars. It c a n be s h o w n that the M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t C o n d i t i o n a n d the H e a d C o n d i t i o n c.q. M a x i m i z a t i o n P r i n c i p l e m a k e d i f f e r e n t claims in instance, b ut n ot by at least are excluded the Head some by cases. the Condition, The Major examples in Constituent since a +m part (18), of c o n s t i t u e n t is c o n t a i n e d in the gap. (18) a. *Peter was i n v i t e d b y Mar y , and Joan John. * P e t e r w e r d u i t g e n o d i g d d o o r Mary, John. for Condition, en Joan a major - 116 - b. This J o h n b o u g h t a litt l e b i t m o r e or a lot . * J a n k o c h t e e n b e e t j e m e e r of e e n h e l e b o e l Mé t - implies preferred that the unless Major Constituent independently b r o u g h t up to e x c l u d e C o n d i t i o n s h o u l d be motivated constraints (18), are ■ 1.3. V A R I A T I O N S O N A - O V E R - A The A-over-A Principle, defined in Chomsky to a (1973, 235) as (19) If a transformation applies structure of the form where a l or - - Ia - - - I •••! a c y c l i c node, t h e n it m u s t be so is p r e t e d as to a p p l y inter to the m a x i m a l p h r a s e o f 'the type A. ca n be u s e d as a c o n d i t i o n w h i c h the M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t some instances. applied An example to the a m b i g u o u s (21a) o r (21b) forces the s a m e r e s u l t s as C o n d i t i o n - at l e a s t f o r s o m e r u l e s in is (20), ( C h o m s k y 1964, the which rule of WH-movement, is s t r u c t u r e d e i t h e r as 44). (20) I saw the b o y w a l k i n g t o w a r d the r a i l r o a d s t a t i o n . (21) a. I saw lwp l^pthe b o y I ^ w a l k i n g t o w a r d the r a i l r o a d station]| b. I saw l^pthe boyl IADV Is w a l k i n g t o w a r d the r a i l r o a d s t a t i o n |] The unambiguity of (22) r e v e a l s tha t W H - m o v e m e n t the b o y in (21b), b ut n ot in (21a): applies to - 117 - (22) Who did I see walking toward the ■ iroad station' Both the Major Constituent Condition . " a n Q the A - o v e r - A P r i n c i ple are able to a cc ou n t for the mi.» „ . „ , , , , N c o r rect d i s t i n c t i o n s . T h e d e r i v a t i o n of (.22) from (21a) is exoi,,^ ... , , ded by the M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t Condition, because I,lr,the ■ h™, I . . NP— - H S ï l is not a m a j o r c o n stituent. The same derivation is p » p i , ^ , . J-Uded by the A - o v e r - A P r i n c i p l e because MDthe boy is dominât-.*-, NP-------Ufnm a t e d by a n o t h e r N P Since the structural description ^ P ion o f G a p p i n g ( 1 ) l a c k s c o n s t a n t categories, (19) is i n a p p l i n a M , P able to o u r f o r m u l a t i o n of Gapping. In Sag (1976, 278), however *■ „ . > a formulation of Gapping is presented which s p e c i f i c .. 0 the shape of the r e m n a n t s (cf. (29) in chapter 2); the«» , . . , are c o n s t i t u e n t s w i t h two bars (the maximal number of bars i \ c . n Sag's f r a m e w o r k ) , b u c h a structural description makes i t .. , p o s s i b l e to i n v o k e the A - o v e r - A condition, since onlv 0 * ne maximal X consti t u ents m a y function as remnants. FvPr, ^ * then, h o w e v e r , the A - o v e r - A Principle misapplies unless s n » ^ n T , .. Pecial p r o v i s i o n s a r e made. In order to see this, consider , ucture (23 ) ■ Pet e r aa maximal X constituents may fUr,ri~^ "-^ion as r e m n a n t s , #t>::will take place .in no f f f i t r w i l ! be circled N 2 ^ maximal x2 ) (here reneated as * ’ the u n g r a m m a r there repeated as (24)) ls excluded b u t the ’ “’ --the only possible Gapping nn+. g outcome (25) w i 11 Excluded as well. - 117 - (22) W h o d i d I see w a l k i n g t o w a r d the r a i l r o a d s t a t i o n ? B o t h the M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t C o n d i t i o n a n d the A - o v e r - A P r i n c i ple are able derivation stituent to of account (22) The Since constant the Gapping. bars Such the a A-over-A made. Sag Principle of The the M a j o r C o n a major by the con A-over-A Gapping misapplies a formulation the bars in makes it o nly the remnants. In o r d e r to see this, lacks shape of of the these are c o n s t i t u e n t s w i t h of since as (1) to o u r f o r m u l a t i o n however, specifies number condition, Even unless Sag's framework) . possible maximal then, special consider structure to 2 X i nvoke consti however, the provisions are (23): S. Peter sa w If o n l y m a x i m a l deletion will constituents tical 278), which description function (23) same excluded is i n a p p l i c a b l e (1976, maximal structural may is (29) in c h a p t e r 2): (the A-over-A tuents is e x c l u d e d by description (19) presented r e m n a n t s (cf. two distinctions. Ijjpthe b o y | is d o m i n a t e d by a n o t h e r N P . structural In is correct l ^ the b o y l is not derivation categories, Gapping the (21a) because same Principle because of from Condition, s tit u e n t . for X 2 ’ (5) (here time the of H o l l a n d c o n s t i t u e n t s m a y f u n c t i o n as r e m n a n t s , take will -the q u e e n be place (23), circled N repeated only in as 2 2 the a n d V . Thus, (24)) possible since is Gapping u n f o r t u n a t e l y be e x c l u d e d as well. maximal no p X the u n g r a m m a excluded, outcome but (25) at the will - 118 - (24) J o h n saw the q u e e n o f E n g l a n d a n d P e t e r I tM I o f Holland. ■ X* J o h n he e f t de k o n i n g i n v a n E n g e l a n d g e z i e n en P e t e r M i t t / M/MM' iii' ifi v a n N e d e r l a n d (25) J o h n saw the q u e e n o f E n g l a n d a n d P e t e r j^vi the q u e e n o f Holland. J an hee f t de k o n i n g i n v a n E n g e l a n d g e z i e n en P e t e r M i t t de k o n i n g i n v a n N e d e r l a n d ¿ i t t i t In order to come to g r i p s w i t h this situation, Sag p r o p o s e s to a l t e r the A - o v e r - A C o n d i t i o n so as to e x c l u d e (25). The ciple, Bresnan's By the not outcome shares of the this, merits the of Immediate and is constrained choice by Domination narrowly Relativized A-over-A Principle l a t t e r the (24) but not Prin related (Bresnan 1976, to 16). of c o n t e x t p r e d i c a t e s is f r e e (i.e. the A-over-A p r e d i c a t e s m u s t be m a x i m i z e d , Principle), although while relative target to that c o n text. By d e f i n i t i o n , u n s p e c i f i e d v a r i a b l e s are not p r e d i c a t e s (cf. Bresnan 7). 1976, Since the targets of variables,, the R e l a t i v i z e d A - o v e r - A p r i n c i p l e , on t a rget p r e d i c a t e s , The Immediate Relativized twe e n the target notion Principle Principle and context of being are defined is i n a p p l i c a b l e . Domination A-over-A Gapping in is made "min i m a l diverges that the irrelevant, difference" (whi c h from the distinction be a n d r e p l a c e d by in its turn is b a s e d on the d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n v a r i a b l e a n d c o n s t a n t t e r m ) : 1 (26) M i n i m a l d i f f e r e n c e "..., two proper (Sag 1976, analyses 237) differ minimally if e v e r y p r e d i c a t e in the s t r u c t u r a l d e s c r i p t i o n , one, the value of the b o t h p r o p e r an a l y s e s . cates, this m e a n s differing proper that predicate Sinc e variables in all an a l y s e s , is the same for except under are not p r e d i c a s e s o f two m i n i m a l l y a variable term will "cover" a l o n g e r s u b s t r i n g in one t h a n in the o t h er." - 119 - To give an example, according a n a l y s e s of V P - d e l e t i o n to t h i s d e f i n i t i o n ir. (27) the p r o p e r are n o t m i n i m a l l y d i f f e r e n t , since the r e s p e c t i v e v a l u e s of b o t h A U X and V P d i f fer. leave PA 1 W AUX VP PA„ In St.Louis VP AUX (28), only the constant term VP is different, thus P A 1 a nd P A^ are m i n i m a l l y d i f f e r e n t p r o p e r a n a l y s e s . (28) bottle wine PA, PA„ AUX AUX VP VP or drink whisky and - 120 - For m a l l y , the Immediate Domination Principle is stated as follows: (29) I m m e d i a t e D o m i n a t i o n P r i n c i p l e G i v e n two p r o p e r analyses, S with respect to a (Sag 1976, 237) PA^ and P A g , of a s e n t e n c e transformation T which differ m i n i m a l l y w i t h r e s p e c t to the v a l u e of s o m e p r e d i c a t e P in the s t r u c t u r a l (1) /P/ p A d e s c r i p t i o n of T, (the value of 1 P if under P A ^ ) is some t e r m i n a l s u b s t r i n g of t ^ , an d (2) / P / D , is some t e r min a l s u b s t r i n g t 0 , a n d (3) t 1 is a n a l y z a b l e as A^ (A^ C V N T ), an d (4) tg is a n a l y z a b l e as an d (5) (Ag v N T ), c immediately dominates A g , then PA g is an i n a d m i s s a b l e p r o p e r a n a l y s i s o f S with r e s p e c t to T. Th i s p r i n c i p l e ca n be p a r a p h r a s e d as f ollows: (29') If two p r o p e r ana l y s e s , with respect . PA^ and P A g , o f a s e n t e n c e S to a t r a n s f o r m a t i o n T differ minimally w i t h r e s p e c t to the v a l u e of s o m e p r e d i c a t e P in the structural It T, and PAg is follows cates, of d o m i n a t e s p r e d i c a t e Pg of PAg respect relevant description PA^ to an inadmissabl e proper predicate P of immediately, analysis of then S wi th to T . from (29), that predicates only. in Sag's view maximization Since v a r i a b l e s is are n ot predi o it f o l l o w s that fo r G a p p i n g only the r e m n a n t s (X ) are s u b j e c t to (29). The Immediate Domination Principle A-over-A Condition A-over-A (29) ately selects ing) . the dominate variable in two respects: Condition at selects the is d i s t i n c t given dominating two p r e d i c a t e s the predicate, t o p m o s t o n l y if b o t h p r e d i c a t e s e ach l east other, (otherwise an d (ii) a minimal are f r o m the while (i) i m m e d i adjacent difference to is one lack - 121 - This allowed, ever, the implies s ince in do no t the p r o p e r a n a l y s e s circled proper the that t hey VPs analysis possible dominate 2 is outputs (27) proper minimally. differ minimally, e ach o t h e r allowed. of both differ analyses In are (28), how and furthermore, immediately. Thus, only This corresponds precisely VP-deletion in structures such to as (27) a n d (28), c f . : (27') a. P e t e r doe s n o t w a n t to l e a v e St. Louis, b ut J o h n n y does, b. P e t e r does no t w a n t to l e a v e St. Louis, b ut J o h n n y doe s w a n t to. (28') a. ¥r P e t e r does no t b o t t l e w i n e a n d d r i n k b eer, but J o h n n y doe s b. (0), an d d r i n k w h i s k y . P e t e r doe s no t b o t t l e w i n e a nd d r i n k b eer, b ut J o h n n y does. (the In the s t r u c t u r a l d e s c r i p t i o n of G a p p i n g , 2 X remnants) alternate with variables, proper analyses differ minimally. This the p r e d i c a t e s and implies t hus that m o s3tt a ,2 X c o n s t i t u e n t c a n n o t f u n c t i o n as a r e m n a n t if it is i m m e d i a t e l y 2 d o m i n a t e d by aann o t h e r X c o n s t i t u e n t . S a g i l l u s t r a t e s this point with (30) a, (30). * J o h n met the v i c e - p r e s i d e n t of IBM, and Betsy of X e r o x . b. * J o h n o n t m o e t t e de p r e s i d e n t v a n I B M en B e t s y v a n Xerox. He claims NP, cf. ( 3 0 ’) that the PP of Xerox is immediately (30'). NP the v i c e - p r e s i d e n t (N2 ) o f 'Xerox dominated by - 122 - In this ca s e the Immediate Domination Principle excludes of X e r o x as a r e m n a n t of Gapping. 1,4. Sag ti o n SAG VERSUS HANKAMER makes no Principle presents ta ins beats only different effort one an a d j e c t i v e the Major example empirical s k e t c h e d in (32) to s h o w that in claims. phrase Immediate Constituent which both The. e x a m p l e for which (Sag 1976, the Domina Condition. constraints is (31) He make which con S a g c l a i m s the s t r u c t u r e 271): (31) a. C a r o l w a s h a p p y w i t h h e r O l d s m o b i l e , and Margie upset with her Porsche, b. C a r o l w a s u p s e t w i t h h e r O l d s m o b i l e , iiA i ! upset A c c o r d i n g to the p P are correct dominate dition one phrases constituent thus that the with her Porsche 2 Immediate Domination Principle, both A remnants, immediately anot h e r . sentence adjective and Margie w i t h h e r Por s c h e . For (31b) is is (32). since they do not and H à n k a m e r 1s M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t C o n a problem, if the With her Porsche structure is not of a major (it is n o t i m m e d i a t e l y d o m i n a t e d b y S or VP,), a n d Major Constituent Condition incorrectly predicts (31b) wi l l be u n g r a m m a t i c a l . O b v i o u s l y , t h i s p r o b l e m c a n p that P in (32) is n o t d o m i n a t e d be c i r c u m v e n t e d b y a s s u m i n g by AP, but structure. urally, (33) by VP. There may (33) for insta n c e , be would arguments be favoring excluded quite s i n c e the r e is n o V P in p r e n o m i n a l p o s i t i o n . T h e s e h a p p y w i t h t h e i r o l d s m o b i l e s girls. this nat - 123 This shows Domination t hat (31) Principle further examples as a point is in favor unconvincing. indicative S ag of e m p i r i c a l of the does Immediate not present differences between the M a j o r C o n s t i t u e n t C o n d i t i o n a n d the I m m e d i a t e D o m i n a t i o n Principle, a n d it a p p e a r s t hat r e l e v a n t e x a m p l e s are h a r d to c o m e by. A cas e It ha s in p o i n t m a y be f o u n d been argued by Zwarts in i n t e r n a l (1976) that NP-structure. NP-internal PPs e i t h e r take the p o s i t i o n in (34) o r t h a t in (35). (34) (35) spec C o r r e s p o n d i n g e x a m p l e s are: (34') a son o f t h i s w o m a n e en z o o n v a n d e z e v r o u w (35') a b o y w i t h red h a i r e e n j o n g e n me t r o o d h a a r The structural vated PP s difference between in s e v e r a l w a y s . First, the PP of (34) precedes the r e v e r s e is i m p o s s i b l e (36) (34) and (35) c a n be m o t i in e x a m p l e s w i t h b o t h k i n d s o f the P P o f (35) (cf. 37): a son o f t his w o m a n w i t h r ed h a i r e e n z o o n v a n d e z e v r o u w me t r o o d h a a r (37) *a son w i t h re d h a i r o f t hi s w o m a n *een z o o n m e t r o o d h a a r v a n d e z e v r o u w (cf. 36), while - 124 - A second flexives, argument for the distinction and due to B l o m (1977, 394). is Consider based on (38) vs. re (39) (antecedent and anaphor underscored): (38) T h e i r l e t t e r s to e a c h o t h e r w e r e e l i g i b l e for publication. Hun brieven aan elkaar waren voor publikatie beste m d . (39) * T h e i r u n d e r t a k i n g w i t h e a c h o t h e r b e c a m e a succes. * H u n o n d e r n e m i n g m e t e l k a a r w e r d een g r o o t succes. This pattern flexives can can be be e x p l a i n e d u n d e r the a s s u m p t i o n bound only by Daalder and Blom 1975/1976). structure by can PP. be (35), The a superior In s t r u c t u r e that r e antecedent (34), (see t h o u g h not in the s p e c i f i e r is s u p e r i o r to the NP d o m i n a t e d grammaticality differences explained if (34) in (38) and of (38); is the s t r u c t u r e (39) thus and (35) is the s t r u c t u r e of (39). Argument a nd (35) (1974, is three based in f a v o r o f the d i s t i n c t i o n b e t w e e n (34) on anaphoric relations as well. Vergnaud 34) o b s e r v e s that the f o l l o w i n g c o n d i t i o n holds: (40) D i s j u n c t i o n C o n d i t i o n If, in a string, two n o u n a n a p h o r i c a l l y related, phrases NP. a n d N P „ are 1 £ t h e n the s t r i n g m u s t be a n a l y - zab l e as ... N P ..... N P „.. . o r as 1 This c o n d i t i o n (which, anaphora refer description are incidentally, to b o t h NPs, always distinguishing between . . .NP„,. . .NP, . . . . 2 sin c e disjoint) (34) and 2 1 is r e d u n d a n t if r u l e s o f the may (35). (a n a p h o r a n d a n t e c e d e n t u n d e r s c o r e d ) terms of a structural be used Consider as a test for (41) a n d (42) and their c orresponding structures: (41) The s on o f the w o m a n w h o k i l l e d h i m w a s a Nazi. *De z o o n v a n de v r o u w die h e m d o o d d e w a s e e n N a z i . - 125 - (42) T h e b o y w i t h a c o l l a r that s u i t s h i m is a designer. De j o n g e n m e t de trui d ie h e m g o e d s t a a t is een •o n t w e r p e r . (42') ' NP the b o y with a collar that suits (NPj ■ him (41) and (42) Disjunction Condition given The d i f f e r e n c e the structural NP-internal between PPs. w h i l e in (41') Finally, Lightfoot. ed that o ne 1977, 58). In (42') the c a n be e x p l a i n e d by the difference of the two c i r c l e d N P s are di s j o i n t , they a re not. the o u t l i n e of a f o u r t h a r g u m e n t I owe to D a v i d It o n l y h o l d s f or E n g l i s h , w h e r e it h a s b e e n a r g u is the p r o n o m i n a l i z e d f o r m o f N' In the examples (cf. J a c k e n d o f f under consideration one-pronomi- n a l i z a t i o n p r o v i d e s the f o l l o w i n g d i f f e r e n c e : (43) a. *1 m et the s o n o f this w o m a n a n d y o u m et the one of that woman. b. I m e t the b o y w i t h r ed h a i r and y o u m et the one w i t h b l u e hair. These examples indicate that boy in (35') d o m i n a t e d b y N ' , bu t s o n in (34') is not. is exhaustively - 126 - These (34) and fo u r arguments (35), structures For imply the motivate Immediate that the different structures Domination Principle these P P - n o d e in (34), w h i c h is n ot 2 i m m e d i a t e l y d o m i n a t e d by a n o t h e r X c o n s t i t u e n t , is a c o r r e c t Gapping remnant, ately dominated false: both the while by (44), the P P - n o d e N P , is not. in (35), w h i c h is i m m e d i This prediction, which corresponds to (34), however, is a n d (45), w h i c h c o r r e s p o n d s to (35), are u n g r a m m a t i c a l : (44) P e t e r m e t the son o f my n i e c e a n d Ma x ! tfakI$<!i\ of my n e i g h b o r , * P e t e r o n t m o e t t e de z o o n v a n mi jn n i c h t en M a x H iiih v a n mi jn b u u r m a n . (45) * P e t e r m e t a b o y w i t h red h a i r a n d J o h n w i t h b l a c k hair. P e t e r o n t m o e t t e een j o n g e n m et r o o d h a a r en J o h n met z w a r t haar, !i i i M In Hankamer's are excluded: structure Major (35) a n a l ysis, on the other hand, n e i t h e r the P P in s t r u c t u r e . these sentences (34) n o r the PP in is a m a j o r 'c o n s t i t u e n t . T h i s i m p l i e s t h a t the Constituent Condition fi t s the facts more adequately th a n the I m m e d i a t e D o m i n a t i o n P r i n c i p l e . E v e n a p a r t f r o m the o b j e c t i o n tha t the I m m e d i a t e D o m i n a ti o n Principle stituent cannot Condition in be shown to empirical surpass adequacy, the the r e Major ar e Con further p r o b l e m s r e l a t e d to it. O b s e r v e th a t the I m m e d i a t e D o m i n a t i o n Principle is crucially based on the assumption tha t the s t r u c t u r a l d e s c r i p t i o n o f G a p p i n g s p e c i f i e s the r e m n a n t s as 2 ? X c o n s t i t u e n t s . N o t all r e m n a n t s , h o w e v e r , are X c o n s t i t u ents, as s h o w n a b o v e s u c h as ( c h a p t e r 2, s e c t i o n 2.2.) w i t h e x a m p l e s : (46) Bill s a w Harry, not Harry Bi l l z a g Ha r r i e , m a a r H a r r i e Bill. Bill niet. - 127 - In (46) not (met) is a grammatical defect relates remnant, but not a X2 constituent. Another English, which according to to the Sag sentential has roughly structure the shape of of (47) . S’ AUX V' v" " " (i7 ) Tp 2 ) The Immediate Domination Principle predicts that X ' of S' and V' are possible Gapping remnants, daughters of S 2 and it is hard and V 2 are not. This 2 daughters ? X while is a surprising result to think of a reason why this should be true. More seriously, it appears to be in conflict with the facts. By-phrases, for instance, have been argued to be dominated by p (see Williams, 1974). Still, they may perfectly well serve V as remnants of Gapping; (48) The first story was told by Peter and the second story by John. Het eerste verhaal werd verteld door Peter en het tweede verhaal Of course, to door John. one could propose the outcome of Gapping, to adapt constituent structures but that would be a genuine case of putting a cart before the horse. These diate cannot be Condition. some observations conclude Domination shown Principle. to Even worse, well-motivated by-phrases. be As superior our discussion of the Imme indicated, to the this Major principle Constituent it is in conflict with the data, given structures with PP-complements and - 128 1,5. CONCLUSION A comparison of the Head Condition, the A-over-A Principle, and the several versions of Major Constituent Condition reveals that the latter is to be preferred as a constraint on Gapping. ent This is not meant Condition sentence is the grammar as to imply that the Major Constitu better well. constraint It is for obvious other that rules e.g. of the preposition stranding phenomena (the key factor In developing the Relativized A-over-A Condition, cf. Bresnan 1976) still motivate the Relativized A-over-A Principle and the Immediate Domination the Major over-A Principle. Constituent Condition are grammar. It remains izations as to The conclusion Condition valid and seems some to be version that of both the A- constraints' on rules of sentence to be shown whether interesting general their domains of applicability from the investigation of further facts. i will follow - 129 - 2. CONSTRAINTS ON THE GAPS This point ping section will out and consist of three a number of similarities other rules of sentence parts. between grammar. the First I will rule of Gap I will deal with constraints on variables as proposed by Ross (1967), Bach and Horn (1976), and Chomsky recent generalizations Lasnik (1977), Zwarts (1978) between Gapping Strict over these Chomsky fail (1973). (1976 to and account Secondly, I will constraints 1978), fully in Chomsky and Koster for and WH-m o v e m e n t . Finally, show that the (1978b) and similarity I will present the Subjacency Condition as a generalization in line with that proposed by Chomsky (1976) in terms of Subjacency. A cornerstone to the present exposition is the observa tion that the following two sentences are ungrammatical: (49) John said that Peter was ill and ! tth&t John t f & t/ tit, Peter John zei dat Peter ziek was en Peter jL4f/4.&t John • These sentences are excluded neither by the Major Constituent Condition, nor by any of the alternative cussed in the first part of this chapter. me by Riny Huybregts that S Condition: remnants constraints dis It was suggested to (49) can be explained by the Tensed of Gapping may not be constituents of different tensed sentences. 2.1. OBSERVATIONS 2.1.1. SIMILARITIES BETWEEN MOVEMENT AND DELETION Gapping were This will i can originally be shown designed to obey constraints most as constraints of which on movement rules. be illustrated by a comparison of Gapping and WH- - 130 movement. First consider the st ruc t u r a l W, CO M P t______ ^ descriptions of the rules : (50) a. W H - m o v e m e n t Wi b. G a p p i n g A W2 0 Roughly tion), crossed (i.e. the by s tr uc t u r a l observation descriptions arbitrarily long for a hold s is a make string W„ B W3 J 0 disregarding WH-movement A I 0 second Tensed a string st r i n g that ca n cru cia l use ma y that the be deleted of that be Gapping, long string. is sh o w n by the f o l l o w i n g examples: (51) a. i. What d oes J o h n w a n t ? ' i i . John w a n t s be e r and Peter i. wine. Wat wil Jan? i i . J an wil b i e r en Peter b. wijn. i. What d oes J o h n w a n t ii.’ Joh n w a n t s Peter M t t i / t i / M i i. ii. that. J a n wil dit p r o b e r e n en dat i. W hat does J o h n w an t ii. Joh n w a n t s Peter i. ii. and Wat wil J a n p r o b e r e n ? Peter c. to try? to try this, Wat wil to try to be gin ? to try to beg i n i i /t t i /t i this, and that. Ja n p r o b e r e n te b e g i n n e n ? J an wil dit p r o b e r e n te b egi nne n, Peter i t f t ca n gapped. be The the var ia b l e : by W H - c o n s t i t u e n t m a y move ov e r an a r b i t r a r i l y S Condi en dat 4 i ü i f é i i ! t i t ' i i i S ' é é i i ï - and an a This - 131 - d. i. What does John want to try to begin to write? ii. John wants to try to begin to write a n o v e l , and Peter vWrijt i / t a t t i / i i i i i f i t i a play. i. Wat wil Jan proberen te beginnen te schrijven? ii. Jan wil proberen te beginnen een novelle te schrijven en Peter 'Aí XH t W i tir/i! t4 /M & t een toneelstuk Kuno (1976) Linguistic Inquiry (53) which attributes the illustrates to discovery the an of anonymous the pattern same point footnote): (p.317, reader in (52) main - of and text and . (52) a. i. John went out to buy beer, and Bill fried chicken, ii. This is the fried chicken that Bill went out to buy. b. i. John was glad to see Jane, it$.£! t<l! and Bill Martha, ii. There were those who Bill was glad to see, c and those who he was not. c. i. John began singing a chanson, and Bill a Japanese song, ii. The song that Bill began singing was a Japanese song. d. i. John went out singing a chanson, and Bill a Japanese song, ii. The song that Bill went out singing was a Japanese song. - 132 - (53) a. i. John came home to find his wife sick, . his child ii. and Bill My wife, who I came home to find sick, was in a lousy mood. b. i. *Joh'n must be a fool to have married Jane, Bill iMkiiIM14~!ti<bt! t ii. < t > and Martha, *The woman who John was a fool to have married was Jane. c. i. Tom went to Florida to learn to play tennis and Bill M M / U / t W U A / W U A H I H W H squa s h . ii. What did Tom go to India to become? 79 d. i .''John was upset having received A - for the course , and Bill B 9? i i . ' 'What grade was John upset having received for the course? This tween les. indicates (52) To that and give (53) a the explanations (54), are to be WH-movement as well, (54) a. i . of the difference should have a common basis last example, examples discussed by Stillings of . ruled out the for both ru ungrammatical (1975, 270), the be multi-gap (i)-variants by constraints which hold for as shown by the (ii)-variants: A1 was clearly intent on telling Alice to buy the lettuce and Alfred t u u u m n i u m i u ii. u i i n t Jim u / u i / m i u u M t . # He asked who Alfred was clearly intent on telling to buy the lettuce. b. i. *Nancy thought Mike foolish for even talking to Sally and Cindy Alfonse t4>$t n u iu u n tiu iu m . ii. I'd like to know who Cindy thought foolish for even talking to Sally. - 133 - c. i. *John asked George to be the one to inform Mary Sam t<$/y>4 of Ellington's death and Fred M 4 / M 4 / t i! iM & i&l'sM .ti ! <t>t/tlltiAttMf i/ ii. Which friend did he ask to be the one to inform Mary of Ellington's death? ■ft d. i. The box certainly contained thumbtacks before Marty spilled them and the carton 4 4 tt& tiiti pins yi4t<t>t4/ift£-tti / ft. ii. They wondered how many pins the carton certainly contained before Marty spilled them. i, *1 plan to talk to Mary a week from next e. /t i / Tuesday and John ¿.im titt u iM it n M t u iii. to Fred - To whom does John plan to talk a week from next Tuesday? f. i. Arthur put his boa constrictor under the mattress at 80 W.Warren and Bernie plywood 4i^i44t/M4/^4-ttt44/&f,/$0/Yl/yi&ift4rt ■ ii. *He will tell you what Bernie put under the mattress at 80 W.Warren. In view ment some of and these Gapping, well-known similarities between we will review constraints on in the the rules of WH-movefollowing WH-movement in sections order to establish their value for Gapping. 2.1.2. The includes NP THE (COMPLEX) NP CONSTRAINT Constraint Ross' Complex of Bach and Horn NP Constraint, (1976, accounts 280), for the which fact that a WH-constituent may not move out of true NPs: (55) The NP Constraint No constituent that Is dominated by NP can be moved or deleted from that NP by a transformational rule. - 134 - This constraint overlaps to some extent with (i) the Complex movement out of filled NP (cf. (ii) the NP Constraint sentences which Subject Condition (Chomsky Subjacency (Chomsky the Left Branch 1973, Condition 247); by a lexically 250); it prohibits it prohibits movement (59) and (60)); (Ross prohibits movement out of a determiner (56) headed it prohibits (58)); 1973, out of picture noun phrases (cf. (iv) are 70); (56) and (57)); movement out of subjects (cf. (iii) (Ross 1967, 1967, (cf, 13, 114); *Which flowers did John believe the claim that Peter saw? Welke bloemen weersprak Jan de bewering dat Peter gezien had? (57) it (61)): Which flowers did John believe that Peter saw? WeIke bloemen geloofde John dat Peter gezien had? (58) a. *About whom did stories terrify John? *0ver wie maakten verhalen Jan bang? b. About what were books reviewed by Bill? * Waarover werden boeken becritiseerd door Bill? (59) a. *0f whom did Charles lose a picture? Van wie heeft Charles een foto verloren? b. *About what did Bill destroy an article? Waarover heeft Bill een artikel vernietigd? (60) a. Of whom did Charles take a picture? Van wie heeft Charles een foto genomen? b. About what did Bill write an article? Waarover heeft Bill een artikel geschreven? (61) *Whose did you find book? Wiens heb je boek gevonden? - 135 - Problematic the for examples the in NP (60). preposed Constraint Bach PP is and not is Horn the grammaticality claim dominated that sentences the by structure. The difference between (59) and (60) in NP of these in deep thus would be due to a difference of constituent structure: (60' ) NP Charles In Dutch, this a picture difference in of whom constituent structure can be easily motivated by the examples in (62) and (63), which show that NP and PP in (60) are interchangeable, but NP and PP in (59) are not: (62) a. *Charles heeft van Jan een foto verloren. (Charles has of John a picture lost) b. Bill heeft over sex een artikel vernietigd. (Bill has about sex an article destroyed) (63) a. Charles heeft van Jan een foto genomen. (Charles has of John a picture taken) b. Bill heeft over sex een artikel geschreven. (Bill has about sex an article written) It seems that differences in constituent structure may well be the cause of whether or not the PP can be questioned. The pattern gapped sentences, of (56) cf. through (61) can be reproduced in (64) through (69): ft (64) John discussed my question of which flowers they saw and Bill é té iM é é é / é f / A M é tïM ( of) which animals Jan besprak mijn vraag welke bloemen ze gezien hadden en Bill (65) welke dieren John asked which flowers they saw and Bill which animals tttéf /é&é ■ Jan vroeg welke bloemen ze gezien hadden en Bill welke dieren ( 6 6 ) a. ft. Stories about Frankenstein terrified John and about Dracula Peter. ft Verhalen over Frankenstein maakten Jan. bang en over Dracula b. Peter * Books about linguistics were reviewed by Bill and about psychology it é t i / by Peter. *Boeken over linguistiek werden becritiseerd door over psychologie iié fi Bill en door John. (67) a. ft Charles lost a picture of his mother and Peter ta t/ o f his father. ft Charles heeft een foto van zijn moeder verloren b. en Peter m m i 4 u i n u van zijn vader ié f l é ié v I. * Bill destroyed an article about sex and Peter about p o l i t i c s . ft Bill heeft een artikel over sex vernietigd en Peter (68) a. /i i i i ! o v e r politiek Charles took a picture of the queen and Bill Of the king. Charles nam een foto van de koningin en Bill van de koning. - 137 - b. Bill wrote an article about sex and Peter !é - i i í about politics. Bill schreef een artikel over sex en Peter over politiek. (69) John found Bill's book and Peter téúvifi Harry's . *Jan vond Bills boek en Peter féú á Harries The parallelism that the variables constituents NP between on constraint Condition (see Gapping of either both side overlaps 1.1.), and WH-movement rules may not cases relate of a N P - boundary. Note partly with which excludes the shows Major major that the Constituent (58), (59), move out (61), (66), (67)and (69), but not (56) and (64). 2.1.3. THE WH-ISLAND CONSTRAINT WH-constituents sentences, are allowed to of tenseless unless these sentences are introduced by a WH-eom- p lementizer: (70) What did John want to cook today? Wat is Jan van plan vandaag te koken? (71) *What did John wonder when to cook? Wat vroeg Jan zich af wanneer te koken? As regards less Gapping, sentences, see the remnants may be (72), unless, introduced by a WH-complementizer, (72) a. again, in different tense- these sentences are see (73): John wants to cook the meals today and Peter tomorrow. Jan is van plan vandaag eten te koken en Peter morgen - 138 - b. John tried to interview some candidates this morning and Peter ffté é / té / tiïié t'fié 'A /ió rté this afternoon. Jan probeerde vanmorgen met enkele kandidaten te vanmiddag iiéf / praten en Peter (73) a. John wondered what to cook today and Peter tomorrow, Jan vroeg zich af wat vandaag te zullen koken en Peter fté é é / itM / A fliié - t morgen t a u n u / u u t - b. *John asked which candidates to interview this 4é.ii<Ai<^éSéé/té morning and Peter u u n rn this afternoon. *Jan vroeg met welke kandidaten 's morgens te kunnen praten en Peter 's middags H I M 'é i i i t l 'i i 'i . t iii. . The variables of Gapping and WH-movement thus may not contain a WH-complementizer, an assumption which the WH-island Constraint The effects of cf. referred to as 80), the WH-island Constraint tensed sentences as well, (74) is (cf, Chomsky 1977, can be seen in (74) and (75): What did you wonder who he sent? *Wat vroeg je je af wie je gestuurd had? / N * (75) Peter wondered what he sent to Mary, 0< t>ii(dé H é /vi# At / W / pit and John to Sue. Peter vroeg zich af wat hij aan Mary gestuurd had aan Susan m u i x u i m i. en Jan A comparison ants, of however, these reveals examples that and the the non-WH-island ungrammatical Gapping in (75) is due to a more fundamental cause: vari output of - 139 - (76) What did you tell her that you sent to Mary? Wat vertelde je haar dat je aan Marie gestuurd had? (77) Peter told her that he sent something to Mary, and John to Sue. Peter vertelde haar dat hij iets aan Marie gestuurd had en Jan We will Tensed side return aan Susan to these cases below in section 2.1.5. on the S Condition. (76) and (77), In the meantime, WH-movement we conclude that, out and Gapping are sensitive to the WH-island Constraint. (Some native Engli sh which that of example that that (77) speakers doubt in (77). the ungrammatical!ty of the They consider a variant is deleted fully grammatical. is optional are related. in English More will of (77) in Presumably the fact and the semi-grammaticality be said about this below, in section 2.2.5.2.) 2.1.4. THE SENTENTIAL SUBJECT CONSTRAINT Gapping does not obey formulated in Ross (1967, the Sentential Subject Condition 134) as f o l l o w s : (78) The Sentential Subject Constraint No element dominated by an S may be moved out of that S if that node S is dominated by an NP which itself is immediately dominated by S. Compare (80) . the WH-examples of (79) with the gapped sentences of - 140 - (79) a. Who was that the principal would fire (t) expected by the reporters? *Wie werd dat de direkteur (t) zou ontslaan door de reporters verwacht? b. How much bread has that you took been listed by Peter? Hoeveel brood is dat je genomen hebt door Piet opgeschreven? (80) a. Which women the principal would fire was known ti>£t by the reporters and which men y M i i X f l / b y the publishers. Welke vrouwen de direkteur zou ontslaan was bekend aan de reporters en welke mannen $4/ aan de ui tge v e r s . b. How much bread you took has been listed by Peter and how much wine by John. Hoeveel brood je genomen hebt is door Piet opgeschreven en hoeveel wijn ¿ 4 / if i é door John Since (79) is ungrammatical and (80) is grammatical, to maintain the parallelism between in order Gapping and WH-movement an explanation of this difference should be offered. Such an explanation is possible within subject sentences provided by Koster (1978a, several claim tences arguments do not in expand favor from of the subject the analysis of 59). He presents that N P s , but subject rather position E, which is available in root sentences only: sen from a - 141 - The subject sentence S '^ in subject NP position via COMP, no way to (81), derive since (79) there from is linked as indicated in (81). an underlying structure is no COMP position available of the sentential subject. required. E-positlon to the There is such as to the left For Gapping this extra COMP is not The grammaticality of (80) only shows that Gapping applies on E' domains as well. - 2.1.5. THE TENSED S CONDITION Ross' ables: constraints (Ross 1967) (Chomsky 1973) determine which X and Y specified by a rule can be are an island. scope of vari straints the enter the may This yields not define variable in it. a formulated Chomsky's differently: con they involved following formalization of the island character of tensed sentences (Chomsky 1973, 244): (82) The Tensed S Condition No rule can involve X, Y in the structure ... X ... \oe .. Y ...| ... ‘ (1) where Y is not in COMP and a is a tensed sent e n c e . The condition tences embedded are "Y is not semi-islands: tensed sentences in COMP" the is implies that complementizer excluded from tensed position the sen of condition. This proviso is known as the "COMP-escape-hatch". It explains the difference between bounded and unbounded movements obser ved by Ross. COMP position, W H - m o v e m e n t , which may escape, moves a constituent to the but Adverb Preposing and Extrapo - 142 - sition, ves which have no COMP from (83a), but target, (84b) does may not. not derive Thus (83b) deri from (84a) (but rather from a different underlying structure). (83) a. You told me ls lCoMP w h a t l y°u s a w II *________________________ i b. What did you tell me that you saw? (84) a. You told me Ig ICOMP I before d a r k , everybody •t----------------- ^------------------ 1 would leave, b. Before dark, you told me that- everybody would leave. For Gapping, sentences cannot the Tensed contain S Condition claims one of the remnants that but tensed not the other, unless the remnant contained in the tensed sentence is in COMP. This accounts for the difference between ( 8 6 ): (85) and ' (85) a. Charles may decide which boys are coming along and Max which girls &.f$! i'b'thifii,! Karel mag beslissen welke jongens er mee gaan en Max $ , $ . £ / welke meisjes i t h b. The first letter says how much tax you should pay and the second letter how. much V.A.T. In de ene brief staat hoeveel belasting je moet betalen en in de andere brief (86) a. hoeveel BTW ^Charles decided that 20 boys are coming along and Harrie M ü & i& lt é é t 30 girls &f<i/ütitjife/¿ f i j i i . $ Karel besliste dat er 20 jongens mee zouden gaan en Harrie 30 meisjes - 143 - b. *The first letter says that you should pay tax and the second letter V.A.T. In de ene brief staat dat je belasting moet 14$$ I hi BTW betalen en in de andere brief u itm m u . In both (85) sentences, position and but of (86), in the (85) the the remnants one embedded Tensed S Condition. obey , Tensed of the tensed remnants S, and In this respect, S Condition in are in different the is in thereby tensed the COMP escapes the Gapping and WH-movement same way. A difference between these rules, however, was observed in section 2,1.3., above. This difference may be illustrated by (87) and (88) (parallel t o - (76) and (77)). (87) What did Max say that you should buy? Wat zei Max dat je moest kopen? (88) a. *Max said that you should buy bread and Peter wine. * Max zei dat je brood moest kopen en Peter tit! b. i\i wijn To Sue, Max said that you should buy bread and to Ann, w i u n i m u n u i m m i M i wine. # Tegen Susan zei Max dat je brood moest kopen en tegen Ann H i /M&f / / h i In both (87) and (88), X and Y are ...said (Max) that y o u . . . . The in grammaticality WH-constituent tensed in sentence can be (87) to 1. separated by the explanation of the found in successive moves the wijn COMP via of the the COMP divergence cyclicity: of root string the embedded sentence, schematically illustrated in (89): (89) the 10 ,COMP did Max say I,,,COMP you should buy what]] b t__________________ ___ 11_______________________i as - 144 - Gapping is not a cyclicly, and movement rule. hence the It cannot apply successively differences between Gapping and WH-movement as exemplified by (87) and (88) are predicted. In the second original blocking (Chomsky 1973, (82' ) context condition for of the Tensed structure S (82) Condition was a mentioned 244): .. ., (ii) where Y is in COMP and X is not in COMP This of condition COMP clause. to prohibits a Thus, position (in an ad hoc manner) other than the COMP (90) cannot be derived, whereas movement of the out matrix (91) can: (90) *Which dog is believed by Max that Sue saw? (90') |c ,COMP NP is be 1. by Max |c ,C0MP Sue saw wh-dog|| b *____ It__________*________ ____ it______________ i (91) Which dog is it believed that Sue saw? (91') Assume to L ,COMP is it b e l i e v e d l„,C0MP Sue saw w h - d o g 11 “ t_________________________ I■ ‘ t______________ I now that Gapping. remnants X the and Y are in COMP position, (85') will |s , will be (82') is applicable ruled out, tensed since both sentences, but not cf.: •••X... |s , CO m PY 1 •'•II (92) structured as lCO M P X l • • ’ not be ruled out. as (92), (85) in different (s , IC O M P ' ‘ ‘1 On the other hand, (92') C0MP-C0MP condition In this case Is'IcOMPY ••'II Unfortunately, (85) is as grammatical showing that the difference illustrated by (85') and (92') is irrelevant to Gapping: - 145 - (92) a. Who decides which boys are coming along and who M<tt4 a f>f. / i 4>ttt £ f b l i t i'i which girls Wie beslist we Ike jongens er mee gaan en wie welke meisjes i t i u a u m b. Which letter says how much tax you should pay and which letter t & i i how much V.A.T. In welk boek staat hoeveel belasting je moet betalen en in welk boek 41'A’At hoeveel BTW hi ! M i t IM t & liii'? The difference, however, condition account must in 143), He predicts for Gapping. rules relations, see definition of holds follow (1979, rules It the from In that case, also obvious that rules only, COMP-COMP is an (1974, preservingness is and condition for conditions Gapping In fact, Vergnaud structure for movement 19). and rules. by condition. Alternatively, May some examples another deletion rule Sluicing of provided on anaphoric the difference quite naturally and (85) comes as no surprise. Finally, all to movement is COMP-COMP may movement explained, actual a the preservingness movement between direction presents structure only goes to show that the COMP-COMP restricted this which not be material to of might wonder reduction rule with whether by Gapping, and since (1969). (85) there roughly the required proposed by Ross the right (92) effect, This rule of the complementizer. are exists the deletes Its effect can be exemplified by (93): (93) a. Ralph is going to invite somebody from Kankakee to the party, but they don't know who M H IiiU & in iU U U IM ItM liM ti. Ralph neemt iemand uit Kankakee mee naar het • f e e s t , maar ze weten nog niet wie M tlt U iilM U i. f $44/M & t - 146 - b. It is clear that you should pay tax, but you can only guess how much Het staat vast dat je belasting moet betalen, maar je kunt alleen maar raden hoeveel UltMtiytitfrtiii. It seems then that tion of Gapping several the ways fact that that intermediate Sluicing turns ces, Sluicing. this account for (85) stage has and out (92) and (85) can be derived by a combina and it is incorrect. (92) to are optional be most informants shown First, This reject in consider Sluicing as well, rules. for them Sluicing applies such as (93) o n l y . Of. can involve to be grammatical Gapping to be wrong: since and However, the since both prediction these senten in contrastive contexts (94): ?* (94) a.' Charles may decide which boys are coming along and Max may decide which girls £.f<é/ Atérti ■ # ' Karel mag beslissen welke jongens er mee gaan en Harry mag beslissen welke meisjes é f ■ b.' The first letter says how much tax you should pay and the second letter says how much V.A.T, 9* ' In het ene boek staat hoeveel belasting je moet betalen en in het andere boek staat hoeveel BTW hi Second, note exclamations, (95a), nor in that neither Sluicing in the coordinations does not apply in "classical" context (95b) importance (the indirect of Sluicing of such constructions was pointed out by Frans Zwarts in a lecture at the TIN-meeting 1979): - 147 - (95) a. *1 could tell by the color of his hair that he was a lover of music, but I could not tell what a lover of music Ik kon aan de kleur van zijn haar zien dat hij een muziekliefhebber was, maar ik kon niet zien wat een muziekliefhebber fiffchké-i. b. By the color of his hair you can tell what a lover of music he is and by the shape of his cheeks you can tell what a gastronome )hé / t i ■ Aan de kleur van zijn ogen kun je zien wat een muziekliefhebber hij is en aan de vorm van zijn .wangen kun je zien wat een smulpaap Yiti/ié- Gapping in indirect exclamations, on the other hand, is gram matical : (96) By the color of his hair you can tell what a lover of music he is and by the shape of his cheeks ifi'X.Iié.iM tiX X what a gastronome tfié / ■ Aan de kleur van zijn ogen kun je zien wat een muziekliefhebber hij is en aan de vorm van zijn wangen KvM/ h i /i t i t Therefore, Third, wat een smulpaap tyihI té • (96) is a genuine case of Gapping. observe that Sluicing diately contiguous to the COMP node, (97) a. deletes the string imme cf. John knows that the boys are leaving but he does not know when Jan weet dat de jongens vertrekken, weet niet wanneer é i / maar hij / ^ ittti^ é i^ - John knows that the boys are leaving but he does not know when the girls & f i /Xifcfifiè • Jan weet dat de jongens vertrekken, weet niet wanneer de meisjes maar hij . - 148 - The second gap the result of in examples Sluicing. such as (98) Variants "sluiced" gap are ungrammatical, of cf. therefore (98) cannot be with only the (99). 9 (98) 'John may decide when the girls are leaving and /M U M Peter when the boys A f i/ t iA f iiii- Jan mag beslissen wanneer de meisjes vertrekken en Piet (99) . wanneer de jongens *John may decide when the girls are leaving and /ttA ftiii- Peter may decide when the boys *Jan mag beslissen wanneer de meisjes vertrekken en Piet mag beslissen wanneer de jongens The weak grammatical ity presumably due with more than tionally, (98) is citous one. to it of fact the English the third (100), e.g., in Examples remnant (98) is sentences low in quality anyway. Addi must be pointed out limited. example that in English gapped two remnants are highly when the is that are the gapped pattern of relatively contiguous is considered ungrammatical to most the feli second almost univers ally : (100)' John may decide when we will go to Paris and Peter MUM when ybg/i/iitt/&$ to London. 9* ' Jan mag beslissen wanneer we naar Parijs gaan en wanneer 'fii naar London Piet Be this as it may, the comparison of (98) on the one hand and (97b) and (99) on the other strongly suggests that the second gap in (98) is the result of Gapping, not of Sluicing. In sum, the observations in this section show that Gapp ing is a respectable parallels WH-movement shown to be rule of sentence grammar. in important respects: constrained by the Gapping both rules were Tensed S Condition (plus COMP-escape-hatch), the NP C o n s traint, and the WH-island Con straint . WH-movement, but not Gapping, was found to obey the i i - 149 - COMP-COMP but condition, it was claimed to have preservingness follow tion from of an and out an or a the that Sentential recently alternative constraint alternative subject Gapping and pointed source on Condition, latter have (either anaphoric been structure relations), analysis of the structural sentences. WH-movement Subject the If is so, the parallelism adequately or posi between described by the underscored triplet. 2.2. EFFECTS ON THEORY In Chomsky and Lasnik (1977) generalizations grammar over discussed in posed. The partly due partly to Island Constraint movement to the rules. construal (e.g. that previous syntactic and The are of Conditions: Subjacency Conditions rules). The (1978), rules sections constraint Binding Binding on WH-movement Opacity. indexing the and Chomsky constraints on so-called will for the the constraints the show the have sentence been claimed pro to Subjacency, the is apply be and Nominative relevant to to of following proposed generalizations several of fail rules subsections to account parallelism between Gapping and WH-movement observed in the previous section. 2.2.1. SUBJACENCY Subjacency is formulated as follows (Chomsky 1977, 73) (101) Subjacency "... a cyclic rule cannot move a phrase from position Y to position X (or conversely) (6) ...X... where a and |a... |0...Y...| are cyclic nodes. ...| in (6): ...X..., - 150 - In Chomsky (1973) this assumption, int (the (102)), contents but not in (103) (102) S' and NP were assumed to be cyclic. Under Subjacency subsumed of which the Complex NP Constra is represented the NP Constraint schematically in (schematically represented (circled nodes are cyclic)): COMP |s ... I Q . . . I Q COMP |s ... |A <+wh>| ...|||| t..— ______ _________________ It_______________ I (103) COMP |s . . . . . . |pp <+wh>| This implies that in Chomsky (1973) movement of a PP out of a N P , such as in (104) is considered to be the unmarked (un exceptional) case: (104) a. Of whom did John take a picture? Van wie heeft Jan een foto genomen? b. About what did John write an article? Waarover heeft Jan een artikel geschreven? Bach and Horn (1976), ples in ses, no claim (104) are on the other hand, claim that the exam exceptional, and that in the unmarked ca element may be moved out of a NP. They sustain their with examples expository purposes); (105) a. such as (105) (slightly adjusted ■ Of whom did John destroy pictures? # Van wie heeft Jan f o t o 1s vernietigd? b. About whom did stories terrify John? Van wie maakten verhalen Jan bang? c. Of whom did John see Peter's picture? -g. Van wie zag Jan Piets foto? for d. With what did John buy a book? (Answer: With a golden jacket.) *Waarmee heeft Jan een boek gekocht? (Antwoord: As observed moves out difference deep in Met een gouden kaft.) section 2.1.2., of a in structure: structure N P , such such as as for those (104), Bach the examples (106), whereas cases and in Horn (104) (105) where assume will will a PP have have a a (107) as its deep structure: Under this assumption (104) will not be a counterexample to the NP Constraint. In and Chomsky (105) is (1977) accepted this analysis of the grosso modo. He sentences prefers, (104) however, a readjustment rule to account for the difference In structure. This readjustment rule effects the following change (where the original position of PP is indicated by trace t): (108) He saw L m a picture Wr = 7ihe saw |__ of John II rr a picture tl lpp of John I This readjustment is sensitive to: (i) the lexical contents of V (105a); (ii) the position of the NP in the tree: subjects may not be readjusted (105b); (iii) the contents of the determiner of the NP (105c); (iv) the choice of the preposition (105d). and - 152 - Though Chomsky a NP represents tion, He (1977) he the does not puts forward falsify" agrees that marked questioning of a PP out of rather than the unmarked situa agree with Bach and Horn's NP Constraint. examples such it (Chomsky 1977, as (109), which "immediately 112): (109) a. A review was published of Bill's book. [S ,C0MP ls lNP a review t j ... [of B's book|pp || i b. Of the students in the class several failed the exam. [s ,COMP [g [of the students ,.,jpp [Npseveral t^] . . .]] By the NP Constraint, movement of PP out of NP as in (109) is incorrectly prohibited. that is and there other (109)). a movement Again, Subjacency, suggested he of to be this situation, difference rules (such as accounts for this although redefinition On fundamental the the set cyclic. the account of Chomsky between ones exemplified difference is cyclic based nodes: Subjacency will comments WH-movement in on S terms a and in of slight NP are allow movement of a daughter of a NP to any position within S (as in (109)), but not to COMP, (110) which is outside of S: lg 'COMP |/^Ty . . A. ... PP| ...III ______ j ij_____ ƒ. A----------- 5*------ ---1 Nothing is lost by this redefinition of the set of cyclic n o des. The Complex NP Constraint still holds, as shown in (111): (111) [g |COMP |/ ^ V . . ♦ In actual fact, it something • • ■ Is ,COMP [s .. .wh-X. . .1111] __________ It___________1 is gained, Constraint now follows from Subjacency: since the WH-island - 153 - (112) If | COMP g COMP | ... Is .COMP2 | . . .wh-X. . .|||] t h_______________It__________ I I ! ------------- * --------------- 1 is position, filled, X cannot constituent move to COMP^ X cannot either, move since to this this assumes that two cyclic boundaries can be crossed in one swoop. Let cases. us consider Constraints, one from Subjacency there are remnants the the effect Since Gapping obeys the distance (101). that the gappings there between the are as on Gapping Gapping follows On the one hand (113), where from one another, grammatical remnants of however. such in subjacency distance hand Subjacency scope It does not, ungrammatical are other expects of (Complex) NP and the WH-island gappings violates and on where Subjacency, the the as in (114): (113) a. Complex NP Condition *John discussed the question of which roses are to be planted and Peter f i t t t i (of) which appletrees $.ti / t<t/tM *Jan besprak de vraag welke rozen geplant moesten worden en Peter U U U t i U l f t U i welke • appelbomen b . HP Constraint Charles destroyed an article about the moon and t4 about the sun. Peter Karel vernietigde een artikel over de maan en Piet /4 M / o v e r de zon. c . WH-island Constraint * John asked what to write to Mary, and Peter to Sue. *Jan vroeg wat aan Marie te moeten schrijven en Peter aan Susan t i/ M it i'f i - / • - (114) 154 - Subjacency a. Charles seems to believe to be able to say yes, / t<t and John /14 / no. Karel schijnt te geloven in staat te zijn ja i M /t$ / U t i i i i i l fj\ / i t i . i t te zeggen, en Jan t i/ t i& t i b. nee t i l t i i i . i t . John wants to try to begin to write a novel and Sue ' A & t t l t i l t i i I t i l t i t t t l t i l i i t t i i a play. Jan wil proberen te beginnen een novelle te schrijven en Sue een toneelstuk In (113), the only one cyclic node separates the remnants: (Complex) cases. The arbitrary NP examples in amount variable. Constraint of cases (114) in the can be NP in WH-island that an contained in Subjacency is too strong for gappings of type attempts to Constraint derive the granted that no and derivation can be called successful the (114) (113). This shows that the NP-Constraint the from some version of Subjacency has not success, straints S show on the other hand, S-boundaries and too weak for gappings of type with and of the WH-island (yet) met two con if it does not include the Gapping cases. 2.2.2. BINDING CONDITIONS By virtue be of rules can tions on anaphora: taken to be perspective the development considered the antecedent it becomes of trace theory, movement to be constrained by binding moved constituent and anaphor, possible and its respectively. condi trace are From this to exclude both examples in (115) by the same constraint on the relation between they and each other in (a), and they and t in (b): - 155 - (115) a. *They^ believed Tom to have criticized each other. 1 b. Chomsky * T h e y . were believed Tom to have criticized t.. J J (1978) proposes interpretation phrases): of two conditions anaphora the Nominative (empty which nodes Island Condition and Opacity (Chomsky 1978, "bind" and the reciprocal (Chomsky 1978, 48) 17): (116) The Nominative Island Constraint A nominative anaphor cannot be free in S ' . (117) Opacity If a is in the domain of the subject of j3 , P minimal, then a cannot be free in f). "Free" is "unbounded", a abbreviates Chomsky equal for (1978, to i.e. not coindexed with an antecedent. anaphora 13)). (3 is "c-commanded (Reinhart 1976, (pro, S' by". trace, (p.18). "In C-command and the is reciprocal, domain defined as of" is follows 32): (118) C-command Node nor A B c (onstituent)-commands dominates the other and node the B if neither first A branching node which dominates A dominates B. i.e. , a node a is in the domain of a node y if it is dominated by the first branching category dominating y . Nominative sentence, case is assigned to the subject of a tensed but not to the subject of a tenseless sentence. The Nominative Island Condition uses this distinction and prohib its subjects of tensed sentences from being empty. dicts the following pattern: (119) John seems [s , COMP Ig ^NPe ^ to be Jan schijnt ziek te zijn. This pre - 156 - (120) *John seems |g, (that )1 ^NPe I ls illl *Jan schijnt dat ziek is. Both in is no (119) and in antecedent nominative (120) and therefore is free lN p el in S '. In (120), (120), in S', but not but not in (119) since (119) there |N p e) is is excluded by the Nominative Island Condition. In effect c-commanded tenseless the Opacity by subjects, sentences, Condition e.g. holds for constituents Both in tensed and in objects. objects are not allowed to be free in S'. This explains the difference between (121) and (122). (121) It is unclear I„ , („„„„what .1 I„(„„el 5 COMr 1 5 NP [ , |Q0MPw h o il ^s (122) *It is unclear to do t .II l I fjPe HI ^i In both cases t. is bound in S' (by what, and who.); I..„el is i J ---- 1 --- 1 'NP 1 in both cases. In (121) this empty node itself is the free subject, and thereby not in the not excluded by Opacity. (122) is subject in the domain of the domain of the subject, is excluded by Opacity: and INpe| (t ^ ) , and not bound within S '. Since COMP is not in the domain of the subject, it is an exceptional position. It follows that COMP may again function as an "escape hatch". This is shown by WH-movement, which, applied cyclicly successively is the only rule to move if a constituent out of a tensed sentence: In (123) WhOj do you think |g, lC0Mp (124) Whoj do you think |g,lC0Mp ti j| (123), tion, ti is a nominative bound (g t^ is i 11II |g we saw tjl anaphor by virtue t . . in 0 (= S '). The by jl trace of its posi in COMP (t. 1 IJ free in (123) is assumed claims S', not that but not excluded t^ j, this to be .) is ^ !J in the domain of the by Opacity. unlike t^, is In subject, this case, and thus it must be non-nominative. Chomsky so by stipulating that movement rules move - 157 - all features of a category, 1978, 48). Still, application of including case features t^ is assumed to be nominative, WH-mo v e m e n t , because the (Chomsky despite the position of t^ is inherently related.to nominative case. In bound (124), in S' influence of replace at t^ is in the domain of the subject (we), but by t . ., and thereby t - escapes from the 1) J JOpacity. In this way, the Binding Conditions least the Tensed S Condition, and the COMP-esca pe -hatch. Let us consider the Gapping. to the either the remnants anaphoric. Binding Nominative it Proper version 1976). An (125), of the Binding Conditions on in are are not it empty, which considered defined antecedent, not rules Binding is case Island Condition or Opacity, are Additionally, recent Gapping relates Conditions so-called anaphor effect There is no obvious reason for Gapping to be subject (Fiengo in e.g., is necessarily the are to obey of said the condition which in c-command to anaphor. c-command since necessarily constrained by the 1974), terms c-commands and not properly The related its of most (Reinhart bind an remnants of as shown by structured as (126): , (125) Which wine to serve has been decided by John and which cheese by Peter. Welke wijn je moet aanbieden is door Jan beslist en welke kaas ¡4/$$$$/$.$##%$$$$/%$ door Peter w a n t. by Peter - 158 - Neither the dominates ating first branching node Ippby Peter I , nor Ippby Peter 1 dominates to be impossible the dominating first l^pwhich cheese 1 branching node IjjpWhich c h e e s e ] . Thus to interpret domin it seems the Binding Conditions as con straints on the remnants of Gapping, For yet another reason it seems the Binding Conditions as such. side the Tensed S cases, the Specified impossible to interpret It was shown above that, out the Binding Conditions also replace Subject Condition. The latter constraint, how ever, does not restrict the application of Gapping. worthwhile to consider this in some detail. 254) the Specified Subject Condition is It may be In Chomsky (1973, formulated as fol lows : (127) The Specified Subject Condition No rule can involve X, Y (X superior to Y) in the structure ... X ... \a ... Z ... - WYV ...| ... where Z is the specified subject of WYV. (Subjects are specified in case they are lexically filled, or by X. a = S' or contain a proform which is not controlled NP) . The examples (128) illustrate the effect of this con straint : (128) a. The men promised me to defeat each other. De mannen beloofden me elkaar te verslaan. b. The men asked me to defeat each other. * De mannen vroegen me elkaar te verslaan. The reciprocal phrase each other (Y) in (128a) to the men (X), since de f e a t . In (128b), the men controls the can be related empty subject of the men does not control the empty subject - 159 - of de f e a t , and therefore, each o t h e r . (128b) the men cannot be the antecedent of is excluded, since the reciprocal phrase cannot find an antecedent. The difference between (128a) and (b), structured as in (128' ) , (1281) a. The men promised me |g, lN p e] to defeat each other| b. The men asked me Iw p el to defeat each otherl is accounted for by Opacity as follows. The reciprocal phrase each other therefore |Npe] is must "binds" in the |<,, domain of be bound in S'. the Being each o t h e r . Lexical properties quire that the men be the antecedent of reby assigning identical subject [N p e] , and the only NP available, of promise lNpe| in (128a), re the indices to the m e n , [N p e | , and each- o t h e r . Lexical properties of ask require that me be the ante cedent of lN p e] in coindexed, (128b). resulting in Me, [N p e] > and each other thus an uninterpretable structure, are since the reciprocal phrase requires a plural antecedent. The Specified in earlier s e c t i o n s , since WH-movement Subject subject cyclic provides Condition, Specified hatch. Subject Condition has not been considered Subject (First Z in Y but it is irrelevant direct can Condition moves (127), boundary. no to evidence be by COMP, made to W H - movement. for the compatible virtue of passing the over Specified with COMP the the escape specified and then it moves to X, passing over the WH-movement thereby does not involve X and Y, where X and Y are separated by both the subject Z and the cyclic boundary). Subject Condition, (129). Gapping appears to if the remnants are disobey the Specified taken as X and Y, cf. (129) a. Today, John wants to try to begin to write a novel, /t t i / and tomorrow, /Wi t t t H i i t t t t a play. Vandaag wil Jan beginnen een novelle te schrijven en morgen een toneelstuk b. Some people want the door to open to the left, and others iiéixff to the right. Sommigen willen de deur naar links laten openslaan en anderen iifttitl< A 4 / naar rechts lé.tiiiléM'é-iti-i-tc. Some people want all doors to open to the left and others ii&M all windows Sommigen willen alle deuren naar links laten openslaan en anderen i i t t t i t /liiit é ! l i t i t alle ramen / ■ The difference between promise and a s k , which illustrates the Specified Subject Condition par excellence be reproduced for Gapping (cf. (130) a. (cf. (128)) cannot (130)): My mother promised me to talk to the director and my father U /U U to the dean. Mijn moeder beloofde me met de (lirekteur te praten en mijn vador met de dekaan b. My mother asked me to take counsel with the director and my father with the dean. Mijn moeder vroeg me met de direkteur overleg te plegen en mijn vader iiit U i/ H / iU iU . met de dekaan - 161 - In fact, this one might present problem. Chomsky (1973, increasingly sentence from Ever since 269 grammar introduction footnote), successful, from constraints the following perspective on the to there derive bound have traces been constraints constraints on of on empty anaphora. From attempts, on rules positions, the in of i.e. beginning, constraints on the scope of WH-movement constituted the pivot of expositions on a result clear how grammar this of discussions WH-movement constrained view should the explanatory value these it obey preceding is might by not similar sections fit obvious only island-sensitive surfaced at same become into on why constraints. not of this approach. As has conditions regular, the it a theory Gapping time and Nevertheless of of or striking Within WH-movement they Gapping sentence less sentence bound anaphora. legitimized rule more do. as The a fully grammar, they parallels between the scope of Gapping and the scope of WH-movement. This and leaves empty positions strain the positions the one, interpretation in rule, in whether will be with questions about these gapped Logical remnants then, of parallels, sentences the Form, will remnants or subject about whether to or will the the -source whether will refer not to variable constraints on the con empty between Gapping and WH-movement as well. Three Zwarts recent (1978), questions, theories made an and i.e. of publications Neijt on (1978b) they considered general attempt Dutch, constraints to derive at have the on Koster (1978b), considered these relevance' of Gapping for sentence grammar. least some Koster constraints on Gap ping from a theory of empty places, more or less in the spi rit more of Fiengo (1974, old-fashioned chapter 4). syntax. Neijt and Zwarts represent They do not use empty places but derive the scope of Gapping from a generally defined scope of the syntactic Zwarts ly), (1978) and will variable. below from We will (sections there articulated version of Neijt discuss 2.2.3. proceed (1978b) Koster and 2.2.4. with a more (1978b) and respective elaborately (section 2.2.5.). I - 162 - 2.2,3. THE BOUNDING CONDITION (KOSTER, The NP Constraint (Bach and Horn, 1978b) 1976) outlawed any extraction from or deletion in N P . This constraint is reform ulated by Koster within NP within that (1978b) unless in order to exclude empty positions they are bounded NP. Koster further (i.e. find such that it applies to N P , A P , PP, this and S'. (13D constraint He defends reinterpreted and generalized NP Constraint principle of core grammar: an antecedent) generalizes this as a fundamental the Bounding Condition. The Bounding Condition 7 cannot be free in (Koster 1978b, 1/3... I-ye] 123) ...I where 0 is a top node. Top nodes are defined as follows: (132) Top nodes (Koster 1978b, A maximal not projection, 105) ' X n , is a top node iff it is immediately dominated by a node Xm (of the same projection type) such that m > n. Since S', S' the is a top Bounding node and Condition since allows language specific exceptions. S', Bounding the Condition empty subject may be If the empty interpreted languages. by This for If the is certain inapplicable is marked a wh-antecedent Koster as <+wh> ing tributional set of picture. with its variation, provisions e.g., it may the top node all "empty straightlaced and non-core that , outside or an muddle in many position" viz. the Bound restrictions grammar, the be His statement makes distinction between core grammar, Condition and, recaptures facts mentioned in the recent literature. an elegant universal top node Is a tenseless interpreted by a controller outside S'. position way empty places occur within the transparent on dis additional original - 163 - A remarkable of top node and Intended consequence is that a "top node", whereas themselves are not. (133) only tion. be the As circled A-nodes a consequence the first below, under count the "bound" conjunct. (135b) bounded the labels The top nodes or by the [^e] in "interpretable" empty positions own (The as empty position however, their ungrammaticality. in the top of the conjuncts In diagram (133) ........ . and A' as of the definition label in the top of a conjunction is A1 considered and the are not top nodes, S-bars by defini (134) the in structures in each which may m e n t i o n e d - in can verb in (135a) separate case explain their (134) and (135) are top nodes) . (134) [g,John hit Mary and Bill (135) a. *[g,John hit Mary and I don't believe Is ,Bill b. the [y e] Sue]] . *[g,John says that he eats an apple and Max Since (v e ] Sue | . [y e] Bounding ls ,COMP Condition lN p e] ly e] a pearl] is weakened . for tenseless sen tences the following structure is allowed: (136) fg |John wanted to invite Mary and Peter Ig.CQMP In the variable in: same lNpel vein, the I-y-e] Sue]] Bounding in Gapping cannot 3 (-y-e| , Condition explains why cover parts of a major phrase, the as - 164 (137) John was standing in front of his house, and Peter Iye I Ipp Ipe I l^jphis car || • Jan stond voor zijn huis en Peter Iy el Ipp lPe I lNpzijn autoll . The Bounding Condition the remnants of thus Gapping, stituent Condition, strongly e.g., it restricts subsumes discussed favorably the the in the form Major of Con first part of this chapter. While the Bounding Condition thus achieves a large meas ure of success, it is less successful in cases such as (138), where it predicts ungrammaticality for a grammatical sentence (in which S' is tensed), and (139) (In which S' is tense- less), where it predicts just the opposite: (138) (139) John asked [<,,which apples he should eat | and Peter (g,which pears [v e| *John wondered Peter |v e| Although one might may follow from Bounding Condition, 1A U X e 1 IVe N |g,who to invite for dinner| |s , |COMpe| object other |N pS| that |y e| for lunch| ‘ and . the ungrammaticality of (139) principles and it is ominous that does not falsify the grammatical (138) shows the very charaeterictics ruled out by the condition. the analysis that we will give in section 2.2.5., (138) and (139) will be seen to follow the In both facts, directly from an appropriately defined notion of Subjacency. The either. S'0 will notion If we "top node" consider be a top node. a itself structure is not such as without problems (140), only the This seems to imply that all Gapping patterns of (141) are allowed. a ' o >1 l3NP V n p I (4n p e b to 1 ¡3NP V NP| I4n p e NP|] V NP 1 [C N P e NP]]] 6 l2 I5n p *[0 ¡I [3NP V NP] 14n p V NP]] l2 !5n p c d l0 ll structure chapter 1, || [3 n p V NP] [4n p e NP]) e *1 l3Np V NPj 10 'I This n p was I4 n p V NP]] discussed section 2.1.6.), by and >2 [5n p e npI [CNP e NP|j] b e n p ! [„NP e NP]]] o CNP V NP||| ^2 ls NP e NP 1 6 V NP]]] l2 I5n p e NP 1 KNP b Williams there (1978) is no doubt (cf. also that the variants (c) - (e) are ungrammatical, cf.: (142) a. John wants brandy and Max y^pi)is beer, or Max brandy and John iié-tti beer. b. John wants brandy and Max iié-tté beer, wants brandy and John c. *John wants brandy and Max wants beer, 'fréiité brandy and John d. or Max beer. or Max beer, *John wants brandy and Max itécfaté beer, or Max ii&iifé brandy and John wants beer. . e. *John wants brandy and Max wants beer, or Max ivk'hii brandy and John wants beer. Furthermore node, one constituent would from if SQ in expect one of structure there the to (143) be conjuncts other. No such phenomenon exists. is rules and the sole extracting insert top a it in the - 166 - The following morals appear warranted. and its auxiliary principles explained earlier by The Bounding Condition cover the several empty position facts alternative principles. The notion "top node" was stretched for coordinated structures in order to bring the Gapping facts under the explanatory scope of the Bounding Condition. gets "excess 124, and content" 1976, 96). In this way the Bounding Condition over its However, competitors the stretched (Lakatos notion 1970, top node runs into serious difficulties if one considers coordinations with more than two conjuncts, rule scope support one defined by this notion enjoys a striking from non-Gapping phenomena, conjunct, principles and of the cf. (143). to exclude (143), Over this above does not this, defined and in spite and And (139)) even solve the lack of such as extractions from if we the unwanted lack of evidence and ((138) such as (141). Furthermore, invoke independent results sketched in (141) the more fundamental problem for the stretched notion "top node". if we allow the notion of its difficulties, top node as some Gapping facts seem to falsify rather then to confirm the Bounding Condition. This relevant ciently quire the criticism if one of supported by "excess content" framework of Koster feels that (1978b) is only independent evidence and (1978b) cannot be is does in order to be acceptable. Koster marginally the Bounding Condition suffi not re Even then, claimed explained why Gapping is a rule of sentence grammar. to have - 167 - 2.2.4. A PROPOSAL BY ZWARTS (1978) A key observation in Zwarts (1978) concerns the follow ing Dutch construction. (144) De veiligheidsagent stond [ „ [ P Q [p ,achter de grootvorstin || . meter] (The body-guard was standing five meters behind the duchess.) The single phrase P 2 vijf meter achter de grootvorstin function as a remnant of Gapping, tioned by WH-m o v e m e n t , cf. cf. can (145), and can be ques (146). - (145) De ene veiligheidsagent stond twee meter achter de grootvorstin en de andere veiligheidsagent ét<tM I o I „twee meter] |pl achter de koningin|] . P Q ' (One body-guard was standing two meters behind the I duchess and the other body-guard two meters behind the queen.) (146) Hoeveel meter achter de grootvorstin stond de veiligheidsagent? (How many meters behind the duchess was the body-guard?) At the same time, a remnant of WH-movement, 2 the Q -phrase within the P Gapping, cf. cf. (147), and can 2 can function as be questioned by (148). (147) De ene veiligheidsagent stond twee meter achter de grootvorstin en de andere veiligheidsagent ét<£M /M /i f i è t i i t é t ï i i ƒ)/ . I 2 I 2drie meter | (One body-guard was standing two meters behind the duchess and the other body-guard meters .) /été-t’A tté three - 168 - (148) Hoeveel meter stond de veiligheidagent achter de grootvorstin? (How many meters was the body-guard behind the duchess?) p The smaller P '-phrase within as a remnant of Gapping, by W H-moveme n t , cf. (149) cf. the P in (144) cannot function (149), and cannot be questioned (150). *De ene veiligheidsagent stond enkele meters achter de groqtvopstin en de andere veiligheidsagent l\l ^ /)/ Ip,achter de koningin|| . (One body-guard was standing several meters behind the duchess and the other body-guard ii£.&/ I (150) behind the queen. ) *Achter wie stond de veiligheidsagent enkele meters? (Behind who was the body-guard several meters?) Zwarts proposes to explain this parallel and Gapping by a constraint variable the may other In this way NP and PP reference, In (148), not at the 2 one P -bracket, same time. the variable boundaries. The unless same holds a it contains 2 for N -brackets. in the rule is made to respect both Let us call this, for the sake of the "Bracket Constraint". order in contain between WH-movement on the variable in both rules: to which explain the the variables grammaticality of (147) and 2 contain a P -bracket, Zwarts adds to this constraint two modifications. First, transforma tions apply to standard factorizations in the sense of Peters and Ritchie leftmost (1973, symbol a left bracket. 57): a factor a right bracket, According to this, cannot W2 as its 2 the leftmost P -bracket in (151) is not included in the variable W ^ : (151) W 2 [ 2 w h - Q 2 contain nor as its rightmost symbol - 169 - As a consequence, sarily leftward, (152) in the given extraction of wh-Q 2 in (148) is neces and cannot be rightward: Wx ( w h - Q 2 W 2 2| W 3 P !I P -------- - 1 ----- X ------ > The from NP. the mirror-image The NP, and the of relative is this clause moved constraint phenomenon rightward. on is Extraposition is right-peripherally contained the It cannot move variable, and l efward, the notion of to contain an standard factorization. (153) It is W. | „ W0 S J W, N || N <---- x ---- 11------- > obvious offensive that there boundary, since will - be variables WH-movement and Extraposition are defined as in (154) and (155). (1 5 4 ) WH-movement W E W2 (Zwarts 1978, X2 366) W3 +W 1 2 14 3 3 4 5 0 5 (155) Extraposition (Zwarts 1978, 373) s2 W 1 2 1 0 W1 S2 W 3 4 5 3 2 5 2 3 Zwarts is forced to add therefore, variable tions, holds i.e. only for that the constraint on the variables between specified posi for W „ , and not for W- and W 0 In (154) and (155). d I d _ This is the second modification of the Bracket Constraint. - 170 - it We have four objections against Zwarts' analysis. First, 2 possible to extract a Q -phrase from NP in Dutch. is not Just as English PP and NP, Dutch NP is closed. (156) *Ik weet niet | hoeveel kilol hij [ ___ andijvie) Q 4_________________ N ! koopt. (I know not how many pounds he endive buys) Ik kocht vijf kilo andijvie en híj M i t t (157) [ [ zes kilo] é - M ï^ ïé ] . N Q (I bought five pounds (of) endive and he six pounds M l/ 4 t< tti4 - ) The grammaticality of (157) that cf. the deletion is a surprise until one realizes of andijvie does not result from Gapping, (158), (158) Ik koop vijf kilo andijvie als ik weet dat jij l „| „zes kilo] A t è iii't ê ] koopt. N Q ■ (I buy five pounds (of) endive if I know that you six pounds l i t i / The adherence of the some of version "nouny" the i v buy.) QP to its NP cannot follow from A-over-A Constraint, since a deeper embedded QP cannot be a remnant either: (159) *Jan fotografeert twintig meter hoge torens en Piet ié M t t& té iit | „[ pl odertig meter] t é t i I\! t é t i t ü N A N (John photographs twenty meters high towers and Peter i> tét4 if$ 4 ti thirty meters t i i t l t i i i è t é • ) One might object that this is a straw man to begin with since clearly the NP does not to be subject Bach and irrelevant to further constraints. Horn's to offend Zwarts' NP the for Dutch PP only. Constraint, discussion, the and proposal, but appears But if these add up to NP the constituent constraint will will be hold - 171 - Second, such as according to the Bracket Constraint, achter de grootvorstin gaan staan cannot a string be gapped between two remnants, but in (160) it is, (160) Hij is vijf meter achter de grootvorstin gaan staan bij de eerste wedstrijd en )h ii! ié meter| [ „ | „drie P Q A i t t i t / é i ! i t é i t f é i ' é i i t l / ^/éé-M/été-At bíj de tweede wedstrijd. (He has five meters behind the duchess gone standing during the first game and fii/té-é three meters ïH ttiié t t 4/ This is t4 é é /é i té / é t Até i i é during the second game) a direct counterexample, and it -is not easy to see how Z w a r t s ’ analysis can be modified in order to capture it. Third, consider the following. The Bracket Constraint predicts that the left-peripheral part of a major constituent can function as a second remnant, eral part of a major and that the right-periph constituent can do remnant.4 The gappings presented by Zwarts illustrate the illustrate that former combination. this prediction is Examples false. so as a first ((147) and (157)) with the latter Right-peripheral parts of leftmost constituents never function as remnants: (161) a. * A u t o 's met ronde wielen rijden soepel en /U A M i f é met vierkante wielen N N (Cars with round wheels run smoothly and ii.f i b. stug. with square wheels f v iyi rigid, ) *Kritiek op de dagbladen wordt gepubliceerd in de weekbladen en '/ ¡éfü / |/ Likt i t t 4Vi | ,°P de weekbladen]] N P in de dagbladen. (Criticism on the daily papers is published in the weekly papers and i f i t t ü é f i ié / iM ïié t ii in the daily papers.) on the weekly - 172 - c,*Hij stond enkele meters achter de grootvorstin é/ bij de eerste wedstrijd en / itiÜ-été i ï é t - é f & f l ^ , U | 2 de koningin]|j bij de tweede wedstrijd. (He was several meters behind the duchess during the first game and the queen during the second game) In order to protect Zwarts has the first remnant against the variable, to add the coordinator as a factor of the Gapping rule, as in (162). (162) Gapping c w (Zwarts 1978, X2 1 W2 x2 3 1 2 3 4 5 6 =£> 1 0 3 0 5 0 The first variable is predicted tween specified positions. suspect W 363) reason coordinator can to to behave as if enclosed be However, enter the reasonably this is the only and very coordinator be claimed in the rule. to be relevant The to the recoverability condition, but not so to the issue of possible remnants. The fourth and last counterargument runs as follows, ¿warts1 observations on QP in PP strongly remind one of the COMP-escape sentential hatch on structures. Here as well as in the case of Dutch PP, there is a major constituent in what seems to refer to it may be specifier position. the constituent serve as In both cases the rules may in the specifier to the effect that a remnant of Gapping, cf. and may be questioned by W H - m o v e m e n t , cf, (145) and (163), (146) and (164), - 173 - (163) Ik weet dat Jan zei achter welke grootvorstin je stond en Piet ü i [<,, [ ^ ^ a c h t e r welke koningin] ¿ é / é tM & ï. (I know that John said behind which duchess you were standing and Peter behind which queen I t t i- M M i) (164) Ik weet wel zei [g , (C0M p achter welke koningín] [s , 1C0MP ___ dat] Piet je stond]| (I know behind which queen Peter said that you were standing) The set of observations strongly suggests (145) - (163) and (146) - (165) that Z w a r t s ' analysis has missed a reveal ing generalization. An escapehatch on Ss and PPs in Dutch is in fact proposed by Van Riemsdijk (1978), and it appears that he is on the right track. Again, applies one only if might one object feels notion vis-à-vis the scope not necessarily study, he Zwarts' that that this fourth Subjacency of syntactic position. conspicuously does not WH-constituents out of sentential consideration is a relevant rules, while this is In his clear and detailed discuss the structures, extraction of and Subjacency is not among his topics. Be that the this as Bracket it may, maximal projections (well-known) the following two examples Constraint cannot of S next examples indicate possibly generalize over to NP and PP. The first set of consists of clauses with tenseless embeddings : (165) John wants to try to begin to write a novel, Peter i / M M / t t f / l a play ]]| . Jan wil proberen te beginnen een novelle te schrijven en Peter 'èÌX/Ì>t<Ì>'$,£Ì'<iih/ |g,een toneelstuk té / à é ìfittifé é )} ■ and - 174 - The second set consists of clauses with sentential subjects: (166) Which dress to wear is a problem for Sue, ls ,which tie and for John. Welke jurk je moet dragen is een probleem voor Susan en [s ,welke das voor John. Whatever and further analysis Subjacency, tures and observed for Zwarts the above, at will give parallelism this moment for WH-movement of PP we and fail S-struc- to see the strength of his analysis of Gapping phenomena. 2.2.5. SUBJACENCY REFORMULATED Since the thesis of Ross have been well aware of the (1967), fact generative grammarians that the scope of rules is constrained by a relatively unrevealing variety of structural configurations, known as islands and semi-islands. The notion of Subjacency was introduced to derive the Island Constraints from formal abstract principles. One might say that Subjacen cy and Ross' the Binding theory of syntax This is not be, but were has been about introduced to explain thesis defines what the for the last twelve years. to say that Ross defined what the issues were to his servation ments as Conditions results. Under this view, Ross' work has language, ("this is provided i.e. the terms a grammatical theoretically meaningful to a large by which sentence") factual extent factual can be the ob state interpreted statements ("this is a violation of the Wli-isl and constraint"). In joins this one light, the of the major past decade. that the Its analysis assumed similarities appeal between best handled by a derivative Subjacency. The presented in this section streams of syntactic research of the resides Gapping in and of Subjacency, its basic WH-movement idea are so-called Strict latter gives a unified explanation of the NP - 175 - Constraint, Constraint Gapping 5 tures. the as and Tensed S constraints coindexing Constraint on both rules and Gapping are the and claimed WH-island W H - movement, to share no literature since fea- 2 .2.5.1. PARAMETERS OF SUBJACENCY If (1973), we consider the notion the relevant of Subjacency has received Chomsky different interpretations in a number of ways: (a) the choice of cyclic nodes: NP/S, (b) the number of cyclic boundaries: boundary, N P / S 1', or NP/S/S" ; a rule may cross one or no boundaries at all; ' (c) the position of the cyclic boundary: properly contained in the a boundary not variable does, or does not co unt. These alternatives will be discussed in this order .in the following subsections. THE CHOICE OF CYCLIC NODES As regards the choice of cyclic nodes, all possible combinations of S and NP have been proposed in various recent works by Chomsky. In Chomsky (1973), S' and NP were consider ed to be cyclic; in Chomsky (1976), S and NP; and in Chomsky (1978), and S', S, NP. NP constraint meant to replace the is constant here, since any (Complex) NP Constraint needs to include NPs. Let us both cyclic, consider there lic WH-movement, (167) [s ,COMP the last alternative. If S and S' are is an obvious problem for successive cyc c f .: ls . . . Ig.COMP ______________ |s . . . wh-X ______I . . . |]]| - 176 - Each WH-step bar the first crosses two cyclic boundaries. As for Gapping, the choice of S and S' predicts a difference between (168) and (169): (168) Charles told who said which boys are coming along and |g,who lg,which girls I 111) ■ Karel vertelde wie gezegd heeft welke jongens er mee gaan en |g ,wie [5i f /M i I tA&ii |]]] | [ s ,welke meisjes . (169) Max told that Peter said which boys are coming along and jgJohn ! H'shMi |g,which girls ■ Karel vertelde dat Peter gezegd heeft welke jongens er mee gaan en cyclic ls ,welke meisjes HI • [ Two t [gJohn boundaries (168), whereas only one (S and S') separate the remnants in (S') does so in (169). Both (168) and (169) are grammatical, however. Given (168), let us assume that either S' or S is cyc lic, but not both. The question now arises how to account for the semi-open character of sentences. be any strong However, verb, let since us a priori the reasons to complementizer tentatively assume There do not appear to choose between S' subcategorizes that they are the in and S. matrix the same cyclic domain. This implies that for the time being we will assume that S is a cyclic node and S' is non-cyclic. - 17? - THE NUMBER OF CYCLIC NODES As regards the number of cyclic nodes, present themselves: (a) two alternatives the two speci fied positions may not contain a cyclic boundary, and (b) it may contain one boundary at most. cyclic the variable between the latter option should be chosen sive cyclic WH-movement Additionally, Chomsky the NP boundary: as (171). The (Chomsky (1976) recall the restriction Chomsky argues that in order to allow succes 1974, 3d lecture, 27). offers rules which apply across examples of (109), here repeated of the scope of variables to one cyclic domain will be too strong for these examples. (171) A review Of the (t) was published of Bill's book. students in the class several (t) failed the exam. For gapped sentences, however, of Gapping dary is the opposite holds: the output is ungrammatical even if only one NP- or S-boun- contained in the variable: cf. (112), repeated here as (172). (172) a. Complex NP Condition * John discussed the problem of which roses are to be planted and Peter (of) which appletrees * Jan besprak de vraag welke rozen geplant moesten worden en Peter b. welke appel . bomen NP Constraint * Charles destroyed an article about the moon and A f t i i t i about the sun | Peter . * Karel vernietigde Piet een artikel over de maan en over de zon]N p . - 178 - c• WH-island Constraint * John asked what to write to Mary, and Peter to Sue| g. * Jan vroeg wat aan Marie te moeten schrijven en ls aan Susan U I H d t U Peter Therefore, I will lic boundary. assume that variables may not cross a cyc It follows that the structures in (171) are not derived by a movement rule Moreover, not be This within possible is to a clearcut formulated in in a way suggested by the traces. the present variants the generalize problem: same of Subjacency, it will over Gapping and WH-movement. the scope unadorned of both rules can be observation language islands and semi-islands that we owe to the work of Ross. as we have notions meant suggested such to be as Subjacency superior then obviously have overcome above, no to the and the concept of introduction the Binding Rossian of the observation language can be If, abstract Conditions observation Subjacency of is language, claimed to if it has not done so for both rules, WH-movement as well as Gapping. THE POSITION OF THE CYCLIC BOUNDARIES As to a these Neijt third parameter sections (1978b) it the was we mentioned position argued of in the preliminaries the that cyclic variables boundary. may not In cross cyclic boundaries (there taken to be S' and N P ), unless these boundaries are peripheral. Amherst-Subjacency terms This (Chomsky condition 1974, 3d is formulated lecture, 34) fo l lows: (173) W I la W2 w h e r e : a is a cyclic node and neither nor is empty. in as - 179 - This as explains follows. variable and hand, is S' the In Tensed (174) (174) S Condition plus S' is is peripherally grammatical. internally contained In COMP-escape hatch contained (175), in the on the other in the variable, and (175) is ungrammatical: (174) John said how many girls should go and Bill éé\ \ . |s , how many boys |g Jan zei hoeveel meisjes er moesten gaan en Bill Ut |s , hoeveel jongens |g ! 'éééitéé!iAé-é ]] . (175) * John said that some girls should go and Bill [g, M i t i*i>\\ . ls some boys *Jan zei dat er enkele meisjes moesten gaan en Bill Ui (g, iét ls if enkele jongens ééiiféé/i&M ]|. COMP-to-COMP movement follows, pheral (176) The since in that case S' is peri (Wg is empty): ... COMP ... Complex NP |s , COMP ... Constraint contained in the variable follows, since the NP-boundary is (neither W 1 , nor Wg is empty), cf. ■g. (177) John answered the question which roses he would prefer and Bill Is , which appletrees f i i 11 • * Jan beantwoordde. de vraag welke rozen hij het liefst had en Bill W£$t't<i>4ti:&4/ Ï^ U é H t A é - Î appelbomen f$4 However, this proposal is falsified by the observation that a remnant may be chosen arbitrarily, and thus may accidentally be the constituent adjacent to a cyclic boundary, (178): |g, welke Ï Ï Î &W- as shown in - 180 - * (178) a. John discussed with Peter the question of which car he would like to buy and Max |Np f\i£ / with (of ) ls , which bike M / i n t s M f i / t i M [| . * Jan besprak met Peter de vraag welke auto hij met Max lNp M f f f & i i graag zou kopen en [g, welke fiets * b. I wonder which city Peter thinks you visited and [s i which city f t i i t i $ J] . [g Susan * Ik vraag me af welke stad Peter denkt dat je bezocht en |g, welke stad |g Susan i u u / m m uurnw. From these nants fore, can examples never it belong seems to the proposal of Neijt Subjacency Gapping. cannot Cyclic be obvious different that the cyclic Gapping domains. (1978b) must be rejected: used to boundaries, constrain in no the matter Amherst variable what rem There of position, constrain the applicational domain of rules. 2. 2. 5. 2. STRICT SUBJACENCY As the notion of Subjacency capture the Gapping facts, as it stands is unable to I propose the following version of "Strict Subjacency". (179) Strict Subjacency (first formulation) No rule may involve X, Y in ... X ... [„ ...Y... j ...X... where a is S or N P . (179) The covers the constraint is NP Constraint too general, and the however, Tensed in that S Condition. it excludes WH-movement in a simple case such as (180). i - 181 - (180) [g ,COMP In order IgJohn eats what 11 to remedy this defect, let us assume that the con tents of the COMP nodes influence the applicability of rules. Thus, S is a semi-island, i.e. it becomes a closed such as NP iff its specifier is lexically filled. domain This can be expressed by the following convention: (181) Cyclicity Changing S changes from non cyclic to cyclic in case the immediately preceding COMP is filled; and S changes from cyclic to non cyclic in case the immediately preceding COMP is emptied. Cyclicity Changing accounts for the semi-island character of sentences. S By Cyclicity Changing, is' non-cyclic at the point WH-movement applies, while as a consequence of WH-movement S lexical 1973, will become insertion 39; and cyclic. is Evers Furthermore, cyclic 1975, (Bowers 83), it if we 1972, follows assume 681; that that Schachter an embedded clause is closed in case lexical insertion of the complement izer' occurs. "Unbounded" WH-movement must cyclicly tensed in sentences with an apply successively overt complementizer that or d a t : once the COMP is filled (which is obligatory in the case in Dutch, filtered of tensed clauses out), S counts as a otherwise the output Is cyclic boundary, WH-constituent cannot be moved out: (182) |s , Is ...|s ,dat 4 <-cyel> [s . . .wh-X. . .|]]] <+eycl> 1 --------------- X -------------- and the <+eycl> : ---------------X ----- J------- ----------- insertion of dat at S2 level In tenseless es, lexical COMP is sentences, insertion ruled stances. In out these and in certain English tensed claus of COMP by is optional filters sentences, only and nonfilling under WH-movement special may of circum (though need not) apply successively cyclicly: both options are allowed. The this: WH-island once following Condition a WH-constituent S node follows occupies is cyclic, quite naturally from the C O MP-position, the and no other WH-constituent may be moved out. Strict Subjacency can now be formulated as follows: (183) Strict Subjacency (revised) No rule may involve X, Y in ... X ... where a |a ... Y ... ] ... X ... is HP or a is S iff its specifier is lexically filled. Then consider Gapping. As predicted by Strict Subjacency Gapping may delete over any complementizers are empty, over a S-boundary if number of S-boundaries if the complementizer is filled, as (185). (184) the as in (184), but it may not delete John wants to try to begin to write a novel and Peter u ^ u / i ^ u / m n ^ u / u u ^ / t ^ u / u i u a play |]| . Jan wil proberen te beginnen een novelie te schrijven en Peter |seen toneelstuk t I i t /1 . !t>i H M M in (185) John assumes that he will write a novel and Peter M&t / % / ' b H i a play] . * Jan veronderstelt dat hij een novelle zal schrijven en Peter een toneelstuk As a further illustration, tizer for (186)) tenseless Gapping may clauses not consider the Dutch complemen om ■ If apply om across is the obligatory S - b oundary, (cf. cf. (187): (186) Karel ging weg (om) brood te halen. (Charles went away (for) bread to get) -* (187) Karel ging weg om brood te halen en Peter wijn (Charles went away for bread to get and Peter wine n u m . Even if om is o p t i o n a l , as in (188) Hij probeerde (om) Bernard te imiteren. (He tried (for) Bernard to imitate; he tried to imitate Bernard.) the presence of om in the first conjunct is incompatible with a gap in the second for most speakers: (189) Kees probeerde Harry Presumably, (*om) Bernard te imiteren en / I M ) Fred ■ this pattern is paralleled in English by optional that: (190) John believes (that) the dog is ill. (191) John believes (*that) the dog is ill and Charly 1 M & tl the cat i £ / i f f . - 184 - A similar tial effect can be observed subject (discussed presence of a pronoun in in examples with a senten 2,1.4. above), after which the (d a t ) is optional in Dutch: (192) Welke foto's bijbesteld moeten worden (dat) staat op de achterkant van de radiobode. (Which photos require a repeat order (that) is specified on the back page of the TV-guide) Assume i.e. that dat is in COMP position welke bijbesteld foto's If (cf. Koster 1978a, 61), that the structure underlying (192) is (192'). dat is present, Cyclicity Changing, a remnant dat t^ staat op de achterkant moeten worden the van de radiobode. following and none S is cyclic by virtue of of its elements can function as together with an element outside of S. This can be verified by (193a) and (193b): * (193) a. Welke foto's bijbesteld moeten worden dat staat op de achterkant van de radiobode en welke dia's op het bloknoot in de keuken. (Which photos require a repeat order that is specified on the back page of the TV-guide and which slides H m H u / t m u / é m t / u u / u m u n u on the tear-off pad in the kitchen) - 185 - b. Welke foto's bijbesteld moeten worden staat op de achterkant van de radiobode er. welke dia's V11ï«i i t é ' U ¡-M4 1 H /v*<»f'M’é l éf-M f. op het bloknoot in de keuken. (Which photos require a repeat order is specified on the back page of the TV-guide and I t i M & t / $ t M t / i $! which slides t H$ on the tear-off pad in the kitchen) 2.2.5.3. THE INTERACTION OF GAPPING AND WH-MOVEMENT The however, revised is not version (yet) of fully Strict Subjacency accurate. in (183), Constructions exist where WH-movement and Gapping interact in a perfectly gramma tical w a y , e.g.: (194) Who eats an apple and [g, whoj^ This Here, sentence lg t^ i A t i a pear ||? is incorrectly excluded Gapping leaves by Strict Subjacency. as remnants two constituents which are in different cyclic domains, by virtue of previous filling of the COMP by WH-movement. For such cases, a more sophisticated version of Strict Subjacency is required. It seems that Strict Subjacency can be disobeyed if the constituent outside of the cyclic domain binds a trace within the cyclic domain. Unattractive though this may be, we are forced to add unless-condition to Strict Subjacency: (195) Strict Subjacency (final version) No rule may involve X, Y in ... X ... [ a ... Y ... | ... X ... where a is N P , or a is S iff its specifier is lexically filled, unless X binds a trace t in a , and there is no cyclic boundary between tx and Y. an - 186 - Strict Subjacency resembles the Specified Subject Condition, which contends that X and Y in different cyclic domains can not be related over a subject, unless X controls it. In the same vein, Strict Subjacency forbids a rule to relate X and Y in different cyclic domains, unless X controls a trace within the cyclic domain of Y. This trace-escape hatch predicts that combinations of Gapping and WH-movement obey the pattern of (196), a predic tion which is borne out, as can be verified by (197): (196) a. [S ,wh-Xi |s ... |s , b. |s ... Y ... ti 1 ‘ *lotwh-X, l0 ... Y ... |ol I„ ... t^ S'"“ -'1! 1S • ■ • * • • ■ 1S' 1S • • ■ "i ’ • -IIII * [S ,wh-Xi (s ... ti ... Is , |g ... Y ...])]] c. d. ls|Wh-Xi Is **• Y ••• t i •** (197) a. Is1 Is •••HU What presents did you say that you bought for éé-i/ ftt&f your mother and what presents for your father? Welke cadeautjes zei je dat je voor je moeder gekocht hebt en welke cadeautjes i , £ i / h i / M t / h ^ voor je vader For whom did you say that Peter believed that you should bring wine, and for whom éé-f / P M t M U i l U t U i U I t M f / f M / beer? Voor wie zei je dat Peter dacht dat je wijn in moest schenken en voor wie M t ! U l U t l t i U t m u /m m bier M / M é ê i / i m m w ? * b. What did you say today that Peter bought for his mother and what yesterday M &f /f é t é t /$ i vii # t / 1<t>t /$ i é /M t K i t ? # Wat zei je vandaag dat Peter voor zijn vader gekocht had en wat t i l t hi gisteren i A4>f / 1 i hi\ / i i 0 / /£ i K i i M t /t i $ ? - 187 - * Who did you tell Peter that you believed that he should visit and who M t John n u a u i u t u i u i n u m i M u t i m m * Wie heb je tegen Peter gezegd dat je dacht dat hij moest bezoeken en wie tegen John i é H M / M t / Mitt Hétèité'91? * c. Who thought that he should bring wine and ! tiïé-t/iï-é/ éM'Aïi/t't'ttii beer? who * Wie dacht dat hij wijn mee moest nemen en wie A è é ï h t l bier Méitié<é£f./ d. Who thought that he should bring wine, and who that he should bring beer? Wie dacht dat hij wijn mee moest nemen en wie t&AéM dat hij bier mee moest nemen? This analysis crucially assumes that traces are left behind in argument position, but not in COMP-position (see Huybregts 1976, 348). If a trace were left behind in COMP, the (b)- and (d)-cases of (197) could not be distinguished. The relation between X and Y in (196a) and (196b) above, is structurally identical to (196c) and (196d), respectively, the only difference being the position of the trace. The generalization is that deep structure clausemates may be the remnants surface of Gapping, structure. no It matter may seem how in far this their distance respect, that in the unless-elause introduces the notion of deep structure clausemate, but this clausemateness is by not true. itself is The notion inadequate in deep view structure of the grammaticality of sentences such as (198) and (199). (198) John told me which books were ordered and Peter which journals i i i t i ! Jan vertelde me welke boeken besteld werden en Piet W / pM welke tijdschriften - 188 - (199) Who told you which books were ordered and who which journals i t i i i / Wie vertelde je weIke boeken besteld werden en wie ' H t t i t i . i l h i we Ike ti jdschrif ten The second remnant in these examples is not a deep structure clausemate of the first remnant. that the rule. the two remnants In brief, notion of fall Strict deep It is only after WH-movement under the Subjacency and iMri? scope (195) surface of the Gapping formally represents structure clausemateness, excluding intermediate structure clausemateness. 3. CONCLUSIONS This thesis elaborates on the assumption that Gapping is a relatively almost "unmarked" completely mechanisms. The phenomenon, predictable unmarked in tion this is "Delete". is given "Delete" served was the the undergenerating motivated Adoption of an independently surplus. rule rules 2, in motivated is reflected of over- further requires order to all information in undergeneration. between the support rule principles and the It was ob Adoption of order of an independently remaining requires in beyond undergeneration research. generate overgenerating motivated rule only information incorpora where to result choice direction of the being The basis for this simple formula chapter shown that squeezes in the properties independently character in the rule format proposed: ted from its the to cases. support exclude of the The success of either strategy depends on the appeal of the proposed additional rules or principles. As regards generating rule, Gapping, but presented for the rules added. Here, The implications investigated. the problem of earlier the studies little assumed independent an under- evidence the opposite strategy was pursued. overgenerating rule "Delete" were Part of chapter 2 and chapter 3 in toto bear on of how to filter out the ungrammatical products - 189 - of the rule. aspects of different problem rule tecedent. of the part was were components considered tion The the approached distinguished the relating grammar. modularly: and In the gapped two relegated chapter string to 2, we and its an It was suggested, after Sag (1976), that this rela be primarily governed by recoverability of deletion, defined at the level of Logical Form. The last chapter defended the claim that Gapping con tributes to the theory of sentence grammar. Given a solution to the recoverability problem along the lines suggested, two closely connected questions emerged: mined the shape of the remnants, which principles deter and which constrain the distance between the remnants. For both, familiar constraints were put to versions of use. were reviewed. ever, was As regards the shape the A-over-A Principle, and of the remnants, the Head Condition Hankamers's Major Constituent Condition, how shown to best serve the facts. Constraints on the distance between the remnants of Gapping were shown to equal the familiar constraints on movement rules. Taking this as a point of departure, we developed the following conclusions: (1) Gapping is an island-sensitive rule. Condition (73)), (cf. and constrain (64) the - (68)), Tensed the distance S The (Complex) NP the WH-island Constraint Condition between (cf. (85) and (cf. (86)) the remnants. Any attempt to explain Island Constraints from more abstract principles such as Subjacency and the Binding Conditions should include Gapping. (2) The attempt by Koster (1978b) in terms of the Bounding Condition Constraint (132), by Zwarts (1978) (section 2.2.4. and (1978b) in terms explain Island of a variant Constraints from in terms footnote of 3), Amherst abstract of the Bracket and by Neijt Subjacency, principles to which include Gapping were found to be unsuccessful . (3) There is no reason to expect that Gapping obeys con straints on bound anaphors, and in fact, the relation between the remnants is not governed by the notion of C-command (cf. - 190 - 125). It is therefore a priori impossible to explain the island-sensitivity of Gapping by the Binding Conditions. More specifically, Specified we saw that Gapping is not constrained by the Subject Condition (129) and (130), although it is sensitive to the Tensed S Condition. (4) Finding the Binding Conditions incapable of explaining the island-sensitivity of Gapping, one is tempted to confer the island-sensitivity of the rule upon Subjacency. However, none of the variations of Subjacency proposed in the litera ture (cf. able to Chomsky generalize 1973, Chomsky 1974 and Chomsky over Gapping and WH-movement 1976) (cf. is (113) and (114)), (5) A new variant of Subjacency was proposed and christen ed "Strict Subjacency" ((195), repeated here as (200)). (200) Strict Subjacency No rule may involve X, Y in ... X Y ... ] ... X ... where a is NP, or a is S iff its specifier is lexically filled, unless X binds a trace tv .A in a , and there is no cyclic boundary between t^ and Y. The new facts type (197) of Subjacency based on the led us to consider a new set of interaction between Gapping and WH-movement that turned out to support the proposal. (6) The parallelism between English and Dutch throughout this study strongly suggests the applicability of universal principles in both systems. - 191 - FOOTNOTES TO CHAPTER 3 1. A true counterexample to the Major Constituent Condition in Dutch was brought up by Zwarts (1978): (i) Jan stond 10 meter achter de grootvorstin en Max !M I 5 meter . (John was standing 30 feet behind the duchess and Max The 15 feet phrase stituent, to form 10 meter achter de grootvorstin forms one con cf. (ii). a major S meter in constituent, (i) and thus cannot be argued (iii) reveals that the analysis sketched for (10) is not available for (i). (ii) 10 meter achter de grootvorstin stond Karel. (10 meters behind the duchess stood Charles) . (iii) * Peter stond 5 meter (Peter was standing 30 feet Not all gapped speakers agree with S t i l l i n g s 1 judgements for the examples, discussion: but those grammatical, this does not speakers who accept consider the affect the (i i )-variants the present (i)-variants as grammatical as well. Zwarts' condition runs as follows (1978, 376): "Conditie op yariabele f a c toren: Voor elke passende factorisering (£j, £ i+ 2 » ..£n ) geldt: als £ i+j een variabele factor constante roet factoren zijn, of R (£ i + 1 ) = ) A 1, betrekking tot een • •, £ it Ëj+i» transformatie T is en £ i en £ i+2 dan R(£^+ 1 ) = |A [A 1A ... IA , waar voor genêrlef 1 2 „ m „ ..., m) geldt: A ± = P* of - N ." • • • [A (i m - 192 Translated, the condition says: For each proper factorization (p., p., p. p. JL 1 — 1+ i — 1+ c. ••En ) with respect to a transformation T it holds that: if p. , is •=-1+ 1 constant a variable factors, than ’ factor, either and p. R(p. , ) ^l+l and = p. „ are — 1+ 2 I. I. ... IA 1 lAg IA , or R(pi+ 1 ) = |A ] A ... ]A , where for no A. (i = m 1 2 „m ? 1,,.,, m) it holds that: A^ = P or A, = M , 4. But cf. De Haan (1979) for another view of the impact of peripheral containment on Gapping phenomena. 5. This statement holds only for the small-scale formulation of Gapping ((40) of chapter 2). The extensive formulation of Gapping and coindexing rules are constrained similarly with respect to Antecendency Binding (cf. Huybregts 1976, 345). This condition disallows, roughly, incomplete ante cedents, a trace. For Gapping this implies i.e. that those containing neither the gapped nor the full anteceding string may contain a trace that is not bound within that string. This excludes (i): (i) M i- Jan speelt hiermee en Piet s d a a r (John plays here with and Peter there ybjLf,#; John plays with this and Peter p W ^ / w i t h t Hier and daar in (i) bind a trace in PP as follows (cf. Van Riemsdijk 1978): (ii) Jan speelt [hier], [__mee t .I en 1 rJr 1 Piet [daar]. t .]. The gapped string (as well as the antecedent string) is incomplete: it contains t j . This trace cannot be consider ed one of the remnants, stituents, and t since remnants must be major con is not a major constituent. This ex- - 193 - plains that the only possible gapped variant of (i) is (iii): (iii) Jan speelt [hier ]. L_mee t .1 en ■ 1 rr 1 Piet |daar]^ |ppmee tjl. In (iii) the therefore trace is part does not block of one of the remnants, the antecedent-anaphor and relation of the gapped and the antecedent string. In this thesis, the relation between the gapped part and its antecedent is not a main issue. We will leave this matter at a sketchy Huybregts (forthcoming). stage, referring the reader to ■ 1 Bibliography AKMAJIAN, A. 1973 'The role phoric of focus in the Interpretation of ana expressions', (eds.), in S.Anderson and P.Kiparsky A Festschrift for Morris Halle, New etc., Holt, Rinehart and Winston, York 215-226. BACH, E. AND G.M. HORN 1976 'Remarks on "Conditions on Transformations"', Linguistic Inquiry 7, 265-300“. BLOM, A. 1975 'Against Conjunction Reduction', Linguistics in A.Kraak (ed.) in the Netherlands 1972-1973, Van Gorcum, 128-140. 1977 Assen, ■ 'Het kwantitatieve er' , Spektator 6-7/8, 387-394. BOWERS, J.S. 1972 Grammatical Relations, unpublished doctoral dis sertation, M.I.T. BRESNAN, J.W. 1971 'On ' sentence stress and syntactic transforma tions' , Language 47, 257-281. 1974 'The Position of Certain Clause-Particles in Phrase Structure', Linguistic Inquiry 5, 614-619. 1975 'Comparative Deletion and Constraints on Transfor mations', Linguistic Analysis 1, 25-74. 1976 'On the Form and Functioning of Transformations', Linguistic Inquiry 7, 3-40. - 196 - CHOMSKY, N 1957 Syntactic Structures, The Hague, etc., Mouton. 1964a Current Issues in Linguistic Theory, London, The Hague, Paris, Mouton & Co. 1964b 'The logical basis of linguistic theory', in H.G. Lunt (ed.), Proceedings nal congress of of linguists, the ninth internatio London, The Hague, Paris, Mouton & Co, 914-1008. 1965 Aspects of the theory of syntax, Cambridge, Mass. etc., The MIT Press. 1973 'Conditions and P. on transformations', Kiparsky (eds.), in S. Anderson A Festschrift for Morris Hall e , New York etc., Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 232-286. 1974 'The Amherst Lectures', ques , Université Paris 1976 'Conditions in Documents Linguisti VII. on rules of grammar', Linguistic Ana lysis 2, 303-351. 1977 ' 'On WH-movement', in P.W. Culicover, A. Akmajian (eds.), T. Wasow and Formal Syntax, New York etc., Academic Press, 71-132. 1978 ’On Binding1, unpublished paper, M.I.T. CHOMSKY, N . AND H. LASNIK 1977 'Filters and Control', Linguistic Inquiry 8, 425 504. DAALDER, S . AND A. BLOM 1975/ 'De 1976 structurele positie van reflexieve en reci- proke pronomina', Spektator 5-6/7, 397-414. DIK, S.C. 1968 Coordination. general Its implications for the theory of linguistics, Publishing Company. Amsterdam, North-Holland - 197 - DOUGHERTY, R.C. 1970 'A grammar of coordinate conjoined structures I 1, Language 46, 850-900. 1971 'A grammar of coordinate conjoined structures II1, Language 47, 298-339. EVERS, A, 1975 The transformational Cycle doctoral dissertation, (distributed by in Dutch and German, University Indiana of Utrecht University Linguistics Club). FIENGO, R. W. 1974 Semantic Conditions on Surface Structure, unpub lished Ph.D. dissertation, M.I.T. GRÛSU, A. 1972 The strategic Content of Island Constraints, king Papers in Linguistics No. Wor 13, The Ohio State University. HAAN, G.J. DE 1976 'Containing nodes: a constraint on extraction', unpublished paper, Utrecht University, 1977 'The Minimal String Principle1, Utrecht Working Papers in Linguistics 3, 73-84. 1979 Conditions on Rules: The proper balance between syntax and semantics, Dordrecht, Foris Publica tions . HANKAMER, J . 1971 Constraints on Deletion in Syntax, unpublished doctoral dissertation, Yale University. 1973 'Unacceptable Ambiguity', Linguistic Inquiry 4, 17-68. HANKAMER, J. AND I. SAG 1976 'Deep and Surface Anaphora', Linguistic Inquiry 7, 391-426. - 198 - HUYBREGTS, M.A.C. 'Vragende(r)wi j s : progressieve 1976 Koefoed en A. Evers (eds,), taalkunde', Lijnen theoretisch onderzoek, Groningen, in van G. taal Tjeenk Willink, 303-366. (forthcoming) doctoral dissertation, University of Utrecht. JACKENDOFF 1971 R.S. 'Gapping and Related Rules', Linguistic Inquiry 2, 21-35. 1972 Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar, 1977 X' Syntax: A Study of Phrase Structure, Cambridge, Cambridge, Mass. etc., The MIT Press. Mass. etc., The MIT Press. KEENAN, E.: ,. AND JR.D. HULL 1973 'The logical answers', presuppositions in J.S. Petöfi and of D. questions and Franck '(eds.), Prasuppositionen in Philosophie und Linguistik, Frankfurt, Atheneum Verlag, 441-466. KOSTER, J. 1975 'Dutch as an SOV language', Linguistic Analysis 1, 111-136. 1978a 'Why subject sentences don't exist', ser (e d . ), Recent in S.J. Key- Transformational European Languages, Linguistic Studies Inquiry in Monograph no. 3, Cambridge, Mass., M.I.T. Press. 1978b Locality Principles in Syntax, Dordrecht, Foris Publications. KUNO, S. 1973 'Constraints on Internal Clauses and Sentential Subjects', Linguistic Inquiry 4, 363-385. 1976 'Gapping: A Functional quiry 7, 300-318. Analysis', Linguistic In - 199 - LAKATOS, I , 1970 'Falsification and the Methodology Research Programmes', (eds.), Criticism of Scientific in I .Lakatos and A.Musgrave and the Growth of Knowledge, London, New York, Cambridge University Press. 1976 Proofs and Refutations, Cambridge, London, New York, Cambridge University Press. LAKOFF, G. 1968 Deep and surface grammar, unpublished paper (dis tributed by Indiana University Linguistics Club). LANGENDOEN, D.T. 1975 'Acceptable conclusions from unacceptable ambigui t y 1, in D. Cohen and J.R. Wlrth (eds.), Testing Linguistic Hypotheses, Washington etc., Hemisphere Publishing Corporation, 111-127. LASNIK, H. 1972 Analyses of Negation in English, unpublished doc toral dissertation, M.I.T. LEES, R.B. 1960 The grammar of English nominalizations, Part II of the International Journal of American Linguistics, Volume 26, No. 3. MALING, J.M. 1972 'On "Gapping and the Order of Constituents"', Linguistic Inquiry 3, 101-108. MALING, J. AND A. ZAENEN 1978 'The Nonuniversality of a Surface Filter', Lin guistic Inquiry 9, 475-497. MANASTER-RAMER, A. 1978 'The Position of the Verb in Dutch and German', in D.Farkas, W.M.Jacobsen and K.W.Todrys (eds.), Papers from the fourteenth regional meeting Chica go Linguistic Society, 254-263. MAY, R . 1979 'Movement and binding', unpublished paper. - 200 - MILSARK, G.L. 1974 Existential doctoral Sentences in dissertation, English, M . I .T . unpublished (available from Indiana University Linguistics Club). NEIJT, A.H. 1978a 'Marked coordination in conjunction with the S0VSVO problem', in W.Zonneveld the Netherlands 1974-1976, (ed.) Linguistics in Lisse, The Peter de Ridder Press, 188-195. 1978b 'Constraints on Gapping1, in D. Farkas, W.M. Jac obsen, and K.W. fourteenth Todrys regional (eds.), meeting Papers from the Chicago Linguistic Society, 307-315. PAARDEKOOPER, P.C. 1971 Beknopte ABN-syntaxis, Den Bosch, Malmberg, 4th. print. POSTAL, P. 1974 . On Raising, Cambridge, Mass., M.I.T. Press. REINHART, T. 1976 The Syntactic Domain of Anaphora, unpublished doctoral dissertation, M.I.T. RIEMSDIJK, H.C. VAN 1978 A Case Study in Syntactic Markedness, Lisse, The Peter de Ridder Press. ROSS, J.R. 1967 Constraints on Variables in Syntax, Ph.D. tation, M.I.T. disser (distributed by Indiana University Linguistics Club). 1969 'Guess Who?', Papers from in the R.I. Binnick et. al. fifth regional meeting (eds.,), of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 252-286. 1970 'Gapping Bierwisch and and the K.E. Order of Constituents', Heidolph (eds.), in M. Progress in Linguistics, The Hague etc., Mouton, 249-259. - 201 - SAG, I.A. 1976 Deletion and Logical Form, unpublished Ph.D. sertation, M.I.T. dis (available from Indiana Univer sity Linguistics Club). SCHACHTER, P. 1973 'Focus and relativization', Language 49, 19-46. 1977 'Constraints on coordination', Language 53, 86 103. STILLINGS, J.T. 1975 'The Formulation of Gapping in English as Evidence for Variable Types in Syntactic Transformations', Linguistic Analysis 1, 247-273. STQCKWELL, R.P., P. SCHACHTER, AND B. HALL PARTEE 1973 ’ The Major Syntactic Structures of English, New York etc., Holt, Rinehart and Winston. TAI, J.H. 1969 Coordination Reduction, unpublished doctoral dis- sertation, Indiana University. THIERSCH, C.L. 1978 Topics in German Syntax, unpublished Ph. D. dis- sertation, M.I.T. VERGNAUD, J.R. 1974 French relative clauses, unpublished Ph.D. di sse r— tation, M.I.T. . 'Transformations and the lexicon1, in P .W .Culieo- WASOW, T. 1977 ver, T.Wasow and A.Akmajian (eds.) Formal Syntax, New York etc., Academic Press, 327-360. WILLIAMS, E.S. 1974 Rule Ordering in Syntax, unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, M.I.T. 1977 'Discourse and Logical Form', Linguistic Inquiry 8, 101-139. 1978 'Across-the-Board Inquiry 9, 31-43. Rule Application', Linguistic - 202 - ZONNEVELD, W. 1978 Linguistics In the Netherlands 1974-1976, Lisse, The Peter de Ridder Press. ZWARTS, F. 1976 'Over de Disjunctie kundig Bulletin Conditie op Anafora', Taal van het Nederlands Instituut van de Rijksuniversiteit te Groningen 6, 35-39. 1978 'Extractie uit prepositionele woordgroepen in het Nederlands', in A. van Berkel et Proeven van Neerlandistiek, Groningen, Instituut, 303-399. al. (eds.), Nederlands Index across-the-board, 11, 13, 18, 30-37, 68, 72 Adj-Deletion, 112 Adverb Preposing, 141 all-and-only, 95 alphabetic variance, 100-108 Amherst Subjacency, 178, 180, 189 Antecedency Binding, 192 A-over-A Principle, 114-120, 128, 170, 189 Backward Conjunction Reduc tion, 1, 15, 17, 18, 39 46, 49-51 Binding Conditions, 149, 154-160, 174, 178, 189, 190 Bounding Condition, 162-166, 189 Bracket Constraint, 168, 169, 171, 173, 189 c-command, 155-157, 189 clausemate, 111, 187, 188 coindexing, 96, 175 cojacent, 30 COMP-COMP condition, 144, 145, 149 COMP-escape hatch, 141, 148, 156, 157, 159, 172, 179 Complex NP Condition, 23, 24, 43, 44, 133, 134, 150-154, 175, 177, 179, 189 Conjunction Reduction, 51 Conjunct Movement, 1, 47, 62-66 constant term, 118-119 constituent variable, 21, 76, 107 context predicate, 118 Coordinate Constituent Con dition, 32, 33 Coordinate Structure Con straint, 23, 30-37, 43, 44 coordinator, 1, 2, 6, 25, 59, 62, 172 cyclic boundary, 159 Cyclicity Changing, 181, 184 cyclic domain, 176, 177, 180, 185, 186 cyclic node, 116, 149-150, 152, 154, 175-179, 181, 182 deep structure, 5, 26, 48, 55, 56, 97, 98, 151, 187, 188 Delay, 17 Deletion, 17 descriptive adequacy, 85 discourse, 37, 69 discourse grammar, 37, 38 Disjunction Condition, 124, 125 domain, 87, 89, 95, 106, 107, 141, 155-157 explanatory adequacy, 89 Extraposition, 141 filter, 35, 47, 75, 87 focus, 102, 103, Focus Assignment, 61 Forward Conjunction Reduc tion 1, 17, 47, 50-57 forward reduction, 17, 39 Gapping (formulations), 38, 39, 73, 76, 88, 95, 109, 172 Head Condition, 113-115, 128, 189 identity, 44, 73, 97, 98 - 204 - idiolectal variation, 91 immediate domination, 139, 162 Immediate Domination Prin ciple, 118, 120-123, 126-128 indirect exclamation, 146 147 initial coordination, 1-16, 53-55, 68 interpretation, 96 interpretive rule, 22, 47, 72, 113 interrogative sentence, 69 intonation, 61, 62 Island Constraint, 39, 189 island sensitive, 18, 23, 43, 161, 189, 190 iterative, 70 It-replacement, 55, 72 lambda-operator, 100, 101, 105 Left Branch Condition, 134 Left Peripheral Deletion, 1, 17, 47, 50, 57-62 list phenomena, 58 Logical Form, 89, 100-104, 161, 189 major constituent, 6, 7, 18, 19, 23, 39, 40, 73, 110, 111, 122, 137, 171, 172, 191,192 Major Constituent Condition, 74, 89, 109-113, 115-117, 122, 123, 137, 164, 189, 191 major phrase, 2, 7, 93, 163 maximal phrase, 12, 13, 116 maximal projection, 2, 3, 5, 6, 12-14, 114, 162, 173 Maximization Principle, 115 minimal difference, 118-121 minor projection, 14 minor-image, 17, 169 modular, 87, 96, 189 N-Deletion, 112 negation, 65, 66, 70, 93 N-Gapping, 26-29 No-Ambiguity Condition, 74 77, 82, 85, 96 Nominative Island Constraint 149, 155-157 non-initial coordination, 1 16, 53, 54 Nonleft-Peripheral NP Con dition, 81, 82, 96 NP Constraint, 133-137, 148, 150-154, 162, 170, 175, 177, 180, 189 observational adequacy, 85, 87, 88 one-pronominalization, 125 Opacitiy, 149, 155-157, 159 overgeneration, 86, 87, 188 Passive, 55, 56, 72 phrasal conjunction, 1, 47 49, 55, 86 Phrasal Conjunction Hypothesis, 1, 47-49 predicate, 120, 121 Predicate Deletion Con straint, 72 preposition deletion, 58 preposition stranding, 128 proper analysis, 119-121 Proper Binding, 157 quantifiers, 102, 106, 107 Question-Answer pairs, 102 107 ■ readjustment rule, 151 recoverability, 73, 97-108, 172, 189 Reflexivization, 72 relabeling, 48, 49, 56 Relativized A-over-A Prin ciple, 118, 128 restructuring, 47, 48, 56, 63, 66, 78, 79 Right Node Raising, 17, 41, 42 right peripheral deletion, 17 semi-island, 141, 174, 178, 181 Sentence Conjunction Hypo thesis, 1, 47, 48 sentence grammar, 24, 30, 31, 37-39, 45, 96, 109, 129, 148, 149, 161, 166, 189 Sentential Subject Con straint, 23, 24, 43, 44, 139-141, 149 set-abstraction, 103-107 - 205 - shallow structure, 88, 99, 1 0 0 , 102 simultaneous factorization, 33, 35 SOV, 7-13, 67, 69 Specified Subject Condition, 145-148, 158-160, 186, 190 standard factorization, 168 Strict Subjacency, 109, 129, 174, 180-188, 190 structure preserving, 53, 145, 148 Subjacency, 129, 134, 149 154, 164, 173-175, 178, 180, 189, 190 Subject Condition, 134 Subject Deletion, 56 Subject Interpretation, 56 Substitution Transformation, 56 successive cyclicity, 143, 144, 156, 175, 181, 182 surface structure, 32, 99, 188 surface constraint, 91 SVO, 8, 11, 67 target, 18, 19, 22, 24, 41, 42, 118, 142 Tensed S Condition, 129, 130, 139, 141, 148, 157, 175, 179, 180, 189, 190 Topicalization, 110 top node, 162-164, 166 trace, 75, 99, 100, 151, 154, 155, 161, 178, 185 187, 192 transderivational con straint, 74, 75, 81 Truncation, 79-81 undergeneration, 188 Universal Grammar, 82, 93 variabl e, 18 , 19, 21,, 23 24, 31, 38, 77 , 88 , 95 100, 101 , 118, 120, 121 129, 130, 137, 138, 141 161, 168, 169, 172, 175 177 , 179, 192 variable constituents, 88 Verb Fronting, 10, 11, 68 verb-scrambling, 67 V-Gapping, 27-29 VP -deletion, 20, 2 1 , 72, 98 99, 102, 119 , 121 v_ postposing, 8 V - preposing, 8, 68 Wh -island Constrai nt , 137-139, 148, 152--154, 174 175, 177, 182, 189 33 , 105 WH -movement, 31, 109-193 passim wo rd order, 7-13, 67 X - bar theory, 15, 113 , 114
© Copyright 2024 ExpyDoc