第4講 記号的文法観1:文法と意味 As its name implies, Cognitive Grammar is first and foremost a theory of grammar. Rather surprising, therefore, are the statement to the effect that “Langacker doesn’t believe in grammar – everything is semantics.” Rest assured that CG neither threatens nor denies the existence of grammar. Grammar exists. The issue is rather the nature of grammar and its relation to other dimensions of linguistic structure. (Langacker 2008:5) (1) my conception of language as symbolic in nature extends beyond lexicon to grammar. […] I contend that grammar itself, i.e. patterns for grouping morphemes into progressively larger configurations, is inherently symbolic and hence meaningful. (Langacker 1987:12) 2つの統語論の自律性 (2a) Strong Autonomy: Grammar is distinct from both lexicon and semantics, constituting a separate level of representation whose description requires a special set of irreducible grammatical primitives. No (2b) Weak Autonomy: Grammar cannot be fully predicted from meaning and other independent factors (e.g. communicative constraints). Yes (Langacker 2005:103) 2. 記号的文法観と使用依拠モデルの関 係 a. 記号的文法観 使用依拠モデル (3) For one thing, language is seen as an integral part of cognition, not a separate “module” (hence cognitive linguistics). Moreover, the pivotal factor is meaning, rather than abstract form (hence the symbolic view of grammar). And from these considerations it follows that language is learned through meaningful use, rather than being innate (hence the usage-based approach). (Langacker 2009b: 628) b. 使用依拠モデル 記号的文法観 (4) Cognitive Grammar makes contact with discourse through the basic claim that all linguistic units are abstracted from usage events, i.e., actual instances of language use. Each such event consists of a comprehensive conceptualization, comprising an expression’s full contextual understanding, paired with an elaborate vocalization, in all its phonetic detail. (Langacker 2001: 144) 3. 文法研究のストラテジー (5) (i) a particular construct is shown necessary for the adequate semantic description of multiple phenomena in various languages; 意味=概念内容×把握、把握=認知能力 意味を記述するのにどのような「把握」のタイプが必要 か? (ii) this construct is related to an independently observable cognitive ability; = 理論外・言語外基準、Cognitive Commitment (iii) this same construct proves critical for the explicit characterization of varied grammatical phenomena. (Langacker 2003:242) (i)の道具立てが(ii)にも適用可能 道具立ての有効性、概念的統合、記号的文法観 (6) The description of grammatical structure does not, however, require a substantially different approach or a battery of unrelated constructs, but merely elaboration and further application of notions already introduced in regard to lexicon. (Langacker 1999:20) (5i)は語彙の意味記述のことを言っている。 (7) a meaning consists of both conceptual content and a particular way of construing that content. (Langacker 2008a: 43) (8) construalのタイプ ① specificity (e.g. thing object vehicle truck pick-up truck battered old pick-up truck) ② perspective (e.g. Come/Go on up into the attic!) ③ prominence prominence 1: profile hub, spoke, rim wheel (Langacker 2008a:67)の意 味の違いを記述するのに何が必要か? => 同じもののどの部分を指しているかが違うの では? =>それを表わす道具立てが必要 = (5i) (9) Every expression evokes some conception – simple or complex – as the basis for its meaning. Within its conceptual base, an expression singles out a particular substructure as a kind of focus of attention. This substructure, called the profile, is the one the expression designates (its conceptual referent). (Langacker 2009: 7) • Cf. profiling is the intersubjective focusing of attention induced by symbolization: through the directive force of symbolic expression, the interlocutors momentarily attend to the same entity in the objective scene. An expression’s profile is thus its conceptual referent […] (Langacker 2015: 128) (5ii) prominence 2: trajector/landmark (11) The lamp is above the table. vs. The table is below the lamp. profileは同じだが、意味は違う 別な道具立てが必要 = (5i) tr/lm (10) Crucially, an expression can profile either a thing or a relationship. […] With expressions that profile relationships, a second kind of prominence comes into play. It consists in the degree of prominence conferred on the participants in the profiled relation. There is generally a primary focal participant, called the trajector (tr). This is the participant the expression is concerned with locating or characterizing. Often there is also a secondary focal participant, called a landmark (lm). Metaphorically, we can think in terms of primary and secondary spotlights, which can be directed at different elements within the scene onstage. (Langacker 2009: 7-9) tr/lmの認知的基盤 (12) I suggest that the relative prominence accorded to relational participants is very much akin to the FIGURE/GROUND ORGANIZATION observed in gestalt psychology, with alternate choices of figure being analogous to FIGURE/GROUND REVERSAL. But can we speak of two degrees of figure status, a ‘primary figure’ and a ‘secondary figure’, corresponding to the constructs trajector and landmark? I believe so. […] I therefore posit trajector/landmark alignment for purposes of viable semantic description, and would argue for its psychological validity. (Langacker 2003: 250) (5ii) 4. 文法の意味 = (5iii)の試み (13) 名詞・動詞、主語・目的語といった文法概念は 高度に普遍的なのはなぜか? It is suggested that each such notion can be characterized semantically in terms of both a prototype, valid for central instances, and a schema instantiated by all instances. The prototype is an experientially grounded conceptual archetype […]. The schema resides in basic cognitive abilities […]. (Langacker 2015: 55) =身体経験、基本的認知能力の共通性 普遍性 概念的原型 (14) conceptual archetypes: experientially grounded concepts so frequent and fundamental in our everyday life […]. Here are some examples: a physical object, an object in a location, an object moving through space, the human body, the human face, a whole and its parts, a physical container and its contents, seeing something, holding something, handing something to someone, exerting force to effect a desired change, a face-to-face social encounter. (Langacker 2008a: 33-4) ビリヤード・ボールモデル (15) billiard-ball model: A fundamental cognitive model that conceives the world as being populated by discrete physical objects that move about and interact energetically when they come into contact. (Langacker 1991:545) 4.1. 文法関係:主語、目的語 (16) a. Floyd broke the glass with a hammer. AGs => INSTR => PATo b. A hammer broke the glass. AG => INSTRs => PATo c. The glass broke. AG => INSTR => PATs subject 1 = the head of an action chain (⊂conceptual archetypes) (17) a. I remember my childhood very well. b. We can’t see Mars tonight because of the haze. subject 2 = active participant in an asymmetrical relationship (18) a. A fence surrounds his property (not active) b. Line A intersects line B. Joshua resembles Jonathan. (not symmetrical) subject 3 = the trajector of a profiled relationship subject 3 (schema) subject 2 subject 1 (18) (17) agent (prototype subject) (16a) (16b,c) TREE” (most schematic) TREE’ TREE (prototype) PALM PINE (19) If subjects are properly characterized in terms of primary focal prominence, for objects the evident basis is secondary prominence. (Langacker 2008a: 370) prominence, trajector/landmarkが主語、目 的語という文法概念を規定する上で有効 = (5iii) (20) the grammatical behavior used to identify subject and object do not serve to characterize these notions but are merely symptomatic of their conceptual import. (Langacker 2008a: 364) 例:Xは尊敬語化を引き起こすから主語だ vs. 主語は際立ちを与えられているので、敬意を示 すことができる 4.2. 品詞:名詞、動詞 伝統的な考え方 (21) Something exploded. vs. There was an explosion. 品詞は意味的に規定できない Cf. 統語論の 自律性 非伝統的考え1 (22) We imagine […] that all “verbs” are inherently concerned with action as such, that a “noun” is the name of some definite object or personality that can be pictured by the mind, that all qualities are necessarily expressed by a definite group of words to which we may appropriately apply the term “adjective”. As soon as we test our vocabulary, we discover that the parts of speech are far from corresponding to so simple an analysis of reality. […] The upshot of such an examination would be to feel convinced that the ‘part of speech’ reflects not so much our intuitive analysis of reality as our ability to compose that reality into a variety of formal patterns. […] It is well to remember that speech consists of a series of propositions. There must be something to talk about and something must be said about this subject of discourse once it is selected. […] As the most common subject of discourse is either a person or a thing, the noun clusters about concrete concepts of that order. As the thing predicated of a subject is generally an activity in the widest sense of the word, […] the verb clusters about concepts of activity. (Sapir 1921:119) 非伝統的考え2 (23) おおまかな言い方をすれば、動詞のkissと 名詞のkiss、 kindとkindnessの間に見られるよう な多分「意味的」と呼んでよいと思われるある種 の差は、同一の意味特徴が違った形で「提示」 されている点にあると言えそうである。つまり、 何らかの「意味特徴」における差ではなくて、そ れらの「提示」の仕方に差があるのではないか ということである。(池上 1975:156) 品詞のプロトタイプ (25) For nouns, the archetype functioning as category prototype is the conception of a physical object. For verbs, it is the conception of participants interacting energetically in a “forcedynamic” event […]. Both figure prominently in a more elaborate conceptual archetype which I refer to as the billiard-ball model. (Langacker 2008a: 103) (26) a noun profiles a thing, where a thing is defined abstractly on the basis of its unitary nature, or “oneness”: it is conceived as a single entity, either inherently or because of grouping [=in which a set of connected entities are conceived as a single entity for higher-level purposes]. (Langacker 2015: 58, 47) Consider a recipe, for example. Though it may be written down, a recipe per se does not exist in space. By our abstract definition, however, a recipe is a thing whose constitutive entities are the successive steps involved in preparing some dish. These steps are interconnected and established as a group just by virtue of being conceived as occurring in a certain sequence. They are reified by being conceptualized as a single, unified procedure with the overall goal of eating the dish. (Langacker 2008: 106) (28) a verb profiles a process [= a complex relationship that develops through conceived time and is scanned sequentially along this axis]. (Langacker 2008a: 112) (24) what determines an expression’s grammatical category is not its overall conceptual content, but the nature of its profile in particular. (Langacker 2008a: 98) profileが品詞という文法概念を規定する上で 必要 = (5iii) まとめ 名詞 動詞 プロトタイプ physical object asymmetrical energetic interaction スキーマ thing process 基本的認知能力 (cf. (13)) conceptual reification The capacity to establish relationships and to scan sequentially through a complex structure (30) ニューマイヤーによる批判 a. What insures that inherently relational words like parent […] or temporal processes like explosion […] will surface as nouns and non-temporal, nonprocess words like die […] will surface as verbs? (Newmeyer 2003:275) b. It is hard to imagine how the bold-faced NPs […] could be ‘trajectors’: There are 12 people in the room; It is likely that Tom will be late; The jig is up; Mary regrets that somebody left a hostile message on her machine (ibid., p.276) --> どう応えるか?
© Copyright 2024 ExpyDoc