Mind, Matter and Language Course Guide 2014-2015

Course Guide
Mind, Matter and Language
2014/15
Course Organiser:
Dr Anders J. Schoubye ([email protected])
Course Secretary:
Ms Stephanie Fong ([email protected])
Contents
1.
(Course) Aims and Objectives
2.
Intended Learning Outcomes
3.
Seminar Times and Locations
4.
Seminar Content
5.
PPLS Undergraduate Student Handbook
6.
Readings
7.
Assessment Information
8.
Learn
9.
Useful Information
10. Common Marking Scheme
11. Careers Services 2014/15
12. Feedback
13. Students on a Tier 4 visa
Department of Philosophy
School of Philosophy, Psychology and Language Sciences
Page 1 of 19
University of Edinburgh
1. Course Aims and Objectives
The course is an introduction to the Philosophy of Mind and Language. The objectives
are:
 To introduce students to some of the problems and concepts in philosophy of
language and philosophy of mind that are central to philosophy.
 To develop students’ abilities to understand and be critical of philosophical
argument, by examining in detail some of the key arguments and texts in
philosophy of language and mind.
 To inculcate in students taking this as their only philosophy course an
understanding of the nature of philosophy and an appreciation of the value of
philosophical ways of thinking.
 To provide for students, who will take further philosophy courses, a solid
understanding of these central topics, thereby providing a firm basis for the
development of their philosophical knowledge and understanding.
 To introduce students to characteristically philosophical ways of thinking,
including: the idea of an argument and some of the ways an argument may be
evaluated and analysed; the sorts of evidence that philosophical arguments use,
and the differences between philosophical and empirical ways of thinking; the
analysis and investigation of concepts.
 To enable students to express philosophical ideas and arguments both orally and
in writing, with particular regard to the following qualities: clarity, precision, and
concision; structure in essay organization; structure in argument (written and
oral); the ability to argue effectively in a debate, including showing respect for
other participants.
 To promote the acquisition of generic analytical and critical thinking skills,
including: the ability to identify the argument in a piece of prose; the ability to
approach ideas with an open mind.

To encourage other transferable skills, including the ability to work to deadlines;
use of computers for word-processing and the retrieval of information from the
World Wide Web.
2. Intended Learning Outcomes






Familiarity with the central concepts in the theory of meaning such as truth
conditions, propositions, and compositionality.
Ability to explain and provide cogent arguments for a distinction between the
sense and reference of a linguistic expression.
Understanding the difference between locutionary, illocutionary and
perlocutionary speech acts.
Understanding the standard distinction between semantics and pragmatics.
Understanding the key concepts in the theory of assertion.
Understanding the philosophical positions of dualism, behaviourism, identity
theory, intentional realism, instrumentalism and eliminativism.
Page 2 of 19


Understanding the so-called “hard problem” of consciousness and be able to
critically examine the crucial thought experiments designed to support the claims
regarding its existence.
Understanding the nature of the debate concerning folk psychology and our grip
on other agents' mental states.
3. Seminar Times and Locations
Semester 1
Monday
Lecture Theatre 4
Appleton Tower
13:10 - 14:00
Tuesday
Wednesday
Thursday
Lecture Theatre G.03
50 George Square
09:00 - 09:50
4. Seminar Content
PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE
Week 1: Introduction to Philosophy of Language
Dr. Anders J. Schoubye (15.9, 18.9, 19.9)
Week 2: Sense, Reference, and Rigidity
Dr. Anders J. Schoubye (22.9, 25.9, 26.9)
Week 3: Speech Acts
Dr. Anders J. Schoubye (29.9, 2.10, 3.10)
Week 4: Grice on Meaning
Prof. Aidan McGlynn (6.10, 9.10, 10.10)
Week 5: Grice on Implicatures
Prof. Aidan McGlynn (13.10, 16.10, 17.10)
PHILOSOPHY OF MIND
Week 6: Functionalism I
Dr. Dave Ward (20.10, 23.10, 24.10)
Week 7: Functionalism (cont.), Eliminativism and the Intentional Stance
Dr. Dave Ward (27.10, 30.10)
Dr. Tillmann Vierkant (31.10)
Week 8: Eliminativism and the Intentional Stance (cont.)
Dr. Tillmann Vierkant (3.11)
Andrea Polonioli (6.11, 7.11)
Week 9: Extended Mind Theory
Andrea Polonioli (10.11, 13.11, 14.11)
Page 3 of 19
Friday
Lecture Theatre G.03
50 George Square
09:00 - 09:50
Week 10: Higher Order Theories of Consciousness
Mark Sprevak (17.11, 20.11, 21.11)
Week 11: Revision Week
Dr. Anders J. Schoubye (24.11)
Dr. Dave Ward (27.11)
Dr. Tilmann Vierkant (28.11)
5. PPLS Undergraduate Student Handbook
The PPLS Undergraduate Student Handbook has more information on Student Support
and academic guidance; late coursework and plagiarism; illness and disability
adjustments, and useful sources of advice.
The Handbook can be found here:
http://www.ppls.ed.ac.uk/students/undergraduate/documents/PPLS_Student_Handbook
-Master_Copy.pdf
6. Readings
Week 1
Required Readings:
Gotlobb Frege (1892), “On Sense and Reference”
Reprinted in The Frege Reader (1997) 151-172, ed. Michael Beaney,
Blackwell Publishing
Optional Readings:
Marga Reimer (2009), “Reference”
Stanford Encyclopedia Article, Section 2,
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reference/
Barbara Abbott (2010), Reference
Oxford University Press, 1-25
Week 2
Required Readings:
Saul Kripke (1980), Naming and Necessity
Harvard University Press, 22-104 (Lecture I,II)
John L. Austin (1962), How to Do Things with Words
Oxford University Press, 1-11, 25-39, 94-108 (Lecture I,III, VIII)
Page 4 of 19
Optional Readings:
Barbara Abbott (2010), Reference
Oxford University Press, 99-122
Week 3
Required Readings:
John Searle (1975), “Indirect Speech Acts”
In Syntax and Semantics, 3: Speech Acts, ed. P. Cole & J. L. Morgan, 59–82. New
York: Academic Press.
John Searle (1978), “Literal Meaning”
Erkenntniss, 13:1, 207-224
Optional Readings
William Lycan (2000), Philosophy of Language
Routledge, 144-155
Week 4
Required Readings:
Paul H. Grice (1957) “Meaning”,
Philosophical Review, 66:377-388
Optional Readings
William Lycan (2000) “Philosophy of Language”
Chapter 7, Routledge
Week 5
Required Readings:
Paul H. Grice (1989) “Logic and Conversation”
in Studies in the Ways of Words, 22-41, Harvard University Press
Optional Readings
Wayne Davis (2014) “Implicature”
Stanford Encyclopedia Article, sections 1-9
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/implicature/
Week 6
Required Readings:
Kim, J. (2010) “Mind as Immaterial Substance: Descartes’ Dualism”
Chapter 2 in Philosophy of Mind (3rd Edition), Westview.
Optional Readings:
Kim, J. (2010) “Mind as Behaviour: Behaviourism”
Chapter 3 in Philosophy of Mind (3rd Edition), Westview.
Page 5 of 19
Week 7-8
Required Readings:
Kim, J. (2010) “Mind as Brain: The Psychoneural Identical Theory”
Chapter 4 in Philosophy of Mind (3rd Edition), Westview.
Kim, J. (2010) “Mind as a Causal System: Causal-theoretical Functionalism”
Chapter 6 in Philosophy of Mind (3rd Edition), Westview.
Churchland, Paul (2003) “Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes”
in Philosophy of Mind, Contemporary Readings (2003). Timothy O’Connor (eds.)
Routledge
“The Propositional Attitudes”
in Philosophy of Mind, Contemporary Readings (2003), p. 263-268, Timothy O’Connor
(eds.). Routledge
Dennett, Daniel (1987) “True believers. The intentional stance and why it works”
In Dennett, Daniel. The intentional stance. Also in Philosophy of Mind, Contemporary
Readings (2003). Timothy O’Connor (eds.) Routledge
Dennett, Daniel (1989) “The Intentional Stance”, Cambridge, MIT Press, chapter 8
Optional Readings:
Stanford entry on Eliminative Materialism:
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/materialism-eliminative/#SpeProFolPsy
Gopnik, A. and Wellman, H. (1992) “Why the Child's Theory of Mind Really Is a Theory”,
Mind and Language 7: 145-171.
Gordon, R. (1986). “Folk psychology as Simulation”, Mind and Language 1: 158-171.
Reppert, V. (1992). “Eliminative Materialism, Cognitive Suicide, and Begging the
Question”, Metaphilosophy 23: 378-92.
Dan Dennett: http://www.technologyreview.com/Infotech/19179/
Stich, S. (1991). “Do True Believers Exist?”, Aristotelian Society Supplement 65: 22944.
Week 9
Required Readings:
Clark, A. and Chalmers, D. J. (1998) “The extended mind”
Analysis, 58:7–19.
Sprevak, M. (2009) “Extended cognition and functionalism”
The Journal of Philosophy, 106:503-527.
Chalmers, D. J. (1995) “Facing up to the problem of consciousness”
Journal of consciousness studies, 2(3), 200-219.
Page 6 of 19
Optional Readings:
Adams, F. and Aizawa, K. (2001) “The bounds of cognition”
Philosophical Psychology, 14:43– 64.
Shapiro, L. (2010) “James Bond and the barking dog: evolution and extended cognition”
Philosophy of Science, 77(3), 400-418.
Sprevak, M. (2010). “Inference to the hypothesis of extended cognition”
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41: 353-362.
Fodor, J. (2009). “Where is my mind?”
London Review of Books 31 (3).
Block, N. (1995) “On a confusion about a function of consciousness”
Brain and Behavioral Sciences 18 (2):227-247.
Chalmers, D. (2008). “Foreword to Andy Clark’s Supersizing the Mind”
In A. Clark, Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension.
Week 10
Required Readings:
Armstrong, D. M. (1980) “What is consciousness?”
In The Nature of Mind and Other Essays. Harvester Press, Sussex.
Kim, J. (2006). Philosophy of Mind. Westview Press, Cambridge, MA, 2nd edition. (pp.
216-220)
Rosenthal, D. M. (2002) “Explaining consciousness”
In Chalmers, D. J., editor, Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings,
pages 406–421. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Dennett, D. C. (2002) “Quining qualia”
In Chalmers, D. J., editor, Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings,
chapter 26. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Optional Readings
Lycan, W. G. (1996) “Consciousness and Experience”
MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. (Chapter 2)
Carruthers, Peter (2011), “Higher order approaches to consciousness”
(Stanford Enyclopedia Article)
Carruthers, P. (2005) “Consciousness: Essays from a Higher-Order Perspective”
Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Block, N. (2009) “Comparing the major theories of consciousness”
Page 7 of 19
In Gazzaniga, M. S. (ed), The Cognitive Neurosciences, IV, p.1111–1112. MIT Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Cohen, M. A. and Dennett, D. C. (2011) “Consciousness cannot be separated from
function” Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15, pp. 358-364.
Frankish, K. (forthcoming). “Quining diet qualia. Consciousness and Cognition”
[available from http://dl.dropbox.com/u/2061862/Frankish_Quining diet
qualia_eprint.pdf]
Week 11
No readings, revision week
7. Tutorials
In addition to three course lectures per week, you must attend weekly tutorials. Tutorials
give you a chance to discuss further topics and issues in the course and its lectures.
Tutorials will take place, at times and places to be arranged, during weeks 2 through 11
of the semester.
Attendance at tutorials is compulsory for all students on this course. To be clear, you
must attend these tutorials. The class tutor will maintain a register of attendance.
Unexplained absences will be brought to the attention of your Personal Tutor.
You must sign yourself up for a tutorial group during the first week of the semester.
This is done via Learn. If you find that none of the available groups meet at a time which
is compatible with your timetable, please inform Stephanie Fong, in the Teaching Office
immediately. (Undergraduate Teaching Office G.06 is based in Dugald Stewart Building
on Charles Street, off Bristo Square.)
Any student who has not signed her/himself up for tutorials by the due date of the midterm coursework essay will be deemed to have withdrawn from the course. Students
who miss tutorials may be required to do additional written work.
Further information concerning tutorials will be available on Learn.
8. Assessment Information
This course will be examined on the basis of two pieces of assessed work. These
pieces are as follows:
The Mid-Term Coursework Essay
This counts for 25% of the overall assessment mark.
The End of Semester Degree Examination
This counts for 75% of the overall assessment mark.
8.1 Coursework Essay
Page 8 of 19
The coursework essay is a single 1500 word essay answering a question from an
agreed list of questions.
The coursework essay is due on Wednesday 29th October 2014, by 12 noon.
You should upload your essay electronically to Learn, (use .rls or .doc). Further
instructions will be given on Learn. Please contact Stephanie Fong in the Teaching
Office, if you are having problems uploading your essay.
8.2 Word Policy
The word count of your essay, including footnotes but excluding bibliography, must not
exceed the specified word limit. The precise word count must be written on the
coversheet. Overlong essays will be penalised according to the following rule: 5% of the
maximum obtainable mark will be deducted for every 100 words, or part thereof, over
the word limit. So, exceeding the word limit by 1-100 words incurs a deduction of 5%;
exceeding by 101-200 words incurs a deduction of 10%; and so on.
8.3 Degree Examination
The degree examination is a two-hour examination given under exam conditions at a
date, time and place to be announced later in the term.
Detailed information concerning essay titles, readings, submission procedures and the
Degree Examination will be available on Learn.
8.4 Visiting Undergraduates
The assessment arrangements for visiting undergraduates are the same as for all other
students.
8.5 Re-sit exams
For those failing or missing the exam, a resit examination is held in late August. It is the
student's responsibility to check the resit timetable on the Registry's website
http://www.registry.ed.ac.uk, find the time and location of the resit exam and ensure
they are present for that resit. No formal registration is necessary and students will not
be individually notified of the resit date and location of resit exams.
8.6 Progression to Honours
Progression to Philosophy Honours requires (1) an *average* of 50% across both the
mandatory Philosophy courses standardly taken in the second year, Mind, Matter and
Language (MML) and Knowledge and Reality (K&R) achieved at the first sitting and (2)
a minimum of 40% in each course (MML and K&R) achieved at the first sitting.
9. Learn
This year the majority of courses will use electronic submissions for Honours
coursework. For essay submission instructions please see the instructions on LEARN.
Please note you should not include your name or matriculation number on coursework,
only your exam number.
Page 9 of 19
Exemplar essays
Anonymised exemplar essays for this course have been posted on Learn. These are
essays written by past students that they have kindly agreed us to use. We hope that
they are useful to you. We encourage you to read these essays in conjunction with the
Philosophy-specific marking guidelines. We suggest that you discuss the exemplar
essays with your tutor, think about what works and what doesn't in the essays, why the
essays fell into their grade-band, and how the essays could be improved. It is important
to emphasise that there are many ways for an essay to fall into a particular grade-band.
The Philosophy-specific marking guidelines provide explanation of the many and
diverse ways in which an essay can be a 1st, 2.i, 2.ii, and so on; the guidelines also
make clear that what determines a grade-band is a cluster of properties rather than
necessary and sufficient conditions. The exemplar essays only show one way to
achieve a certain grade; it is not the only way. Note that if you attempt to copy text or
content from the exemplar essays in your own work this would be treated as a case of
serious academic misconduct and would have serious repercussions.
10. Useful Information
10.1 Contact
If you have a query regarding lecture content you should contact the lecturer directly by
email or by visiting during their office hours. Your tutor is also likely to be able to clarify
philosophical/course issues for you or direct you to the appropriate person.
For other specifically academic matters you can contact Dr. Anders J. Schoubye who is
the course organiser. Dr. Schoubye’s office hours and contact details are given below:
Office:
Telephone:
E-mail:
Office-hours (Term-time):
Room 4.05, Dugald Stewart Building
(0131) 650 3958
[email protected]
Thursdays, 10.00-12.00
If you have questions not specifically about lecture content, you should speak to the
Course Secretary, Stephanie Fong whose office-hours and other contact details are as
below:
Office:
Telephone:
E-mail:
Office-hours:
G.06 Dugald Stewart Building
(0131) 650 3628
[email protected]
9.30am to 4.30pm, Monday to Wednesday
10.2 Prizes
Students who perform with excellence in Mind Matter and Language are eligible for the
James Hutchinson Prize.
10.3 Innovative Learning Week (for information only)
Page 10 of 19
In academic year 2013-14 the University is having an extra week of teaching in
Semester 2: Innovative Learning Week, 16-20 February 2015.
Normal teaching slots will be suspended and in their place will be a range of other
activities such as master classes, a research day, a science fair, a Gaelic festival and
guest lectures.
More information click on the below links:
http://www.ed.ac.uk/staff-students/students/studies/innovative-learning
http://www.ed.ac.uk/staff-students/students/studies/innovative-learning/calendar
Page 11 of 19
11. Common Marking Scheme
http://www.ed.ac.uk/schools-departments/registry/exams/regulations/common-markingscheme
A1 90-100
A2 80-89
A3 70-79
B
60-69
C
50-59
D
40-49
E
30-39
F
20-29
G
10-19
H
0-9
Excellent Outstanding in every respect, the work is well beyond the level
expected of a competent student at their level of study.
Excellent Outstanding in some respects, the work is often beyond what is
expected of a competent student at their level of study.
Excellent Very good or excellent in most respects, the work is what might
be expected of a very competent student.
Very Good Good or very good in most respects, the work displays
thorough mastery of the relevant learning outcomes.
Good The work clearly meets requirements for demonstrating the relevant
learning outcomes.
Pass The work meets minimum requirements for demonstrating the
relevant learning outcomes.
Marginal fail The work fails to meet minimum requirements for
demonstrating the relevant learning outcomes.
Clear fail The work is very weak or shows a decided lack of effort.
Bad fail The work is extremely weak.
Bad fail The work is of very little consequence, if any, to the area in
question.
Page 12 of 19
Grade-related Marking Guidelines
Explaining the function of these guidelines:
(1)
These are only guidelines; marking still requires discretion and judgment.
(2)
The guidelines are “bottom up” — each band presupposes that the student has
at least satisfied the criteria laid down under the lower bands. So to get a first, it
is assumed that you at least satisfy all the criteria for a 2-1, etc.
(3)
Each set of guidelines should be understood not as providing necessary and
sufficient conditions for a mark in the band specified. Rather, the guidelines
under each band provide a kind of “cluster” which defines a paradigm of a piece
of work falling within the band in question. A piece of work might deviate from the
paradigm in certain respects but still fall within the band. It might help to explain
the idea of a paradigm being invoked here. By way of comparison, an
ornamental chair (as one might find in a museum, and that is not fit for sitting on)
is a less paradigmatic instance of a piece of furniture than an ordinary sofa, but
plausibly an ornamental chair still counts as a piece of furniture all the same.
This is because it satisfies enough of the criteria in the cluster of concepts
associated with being a piece of furniture, though it satisfies fewer of those
criteria than an ordinary sofa. Similarly, a piece of work might be a less than fully
paradigmatic instance of a 2-1 but still count as a 2-1 all the same.
(4)
Although they are written in a way that might naturally suggest a binary reading,
the guidelines are generally scalar – satisfying each of them comes in degrees,
and is not all or nothing. This is important, and relevant to the “paradigm” point
above, in that doing better with respect to one criteria under a given band could
offset doing slightly less well with regards to another. Also, precisely where
within the band a piece of work is assessed will typically reflect how well the
work does in terms of each of these criteria.
(5)
The guidelines apply most clearly for essays. In the case of exam questions, part
of the exercise will be for the student to work out the extent to which the question
calls for something going beyond pure exegesis.
(6)
For history of philosophy classes, where the instructor explicitly indicates this is
the case, the contrast between exegesis and original argument may be less
clear. In these cases, the original argumentation may be an original argument for
an interpretation or reading of a text, for example. Individual instructors have
some discretion in explaining how the specific details of their course mean these
guidelines should be interpreted. As mere guidelines, they provide only a sort of
“default setting” rather than a one size fits all set of prescriptions, amenable to
only one canonical interpretation.
Page 13 of 19
General Guidelines
 Clarity:
o Is the writing clear?
o Is the grammar and spelling correct?
o Is the language used appropriate?
 Structure:
o Is a clear thesis or position stated?
o Is an argument, or arguments, offered in support of the thesis?
o Does each part of the essay/exam have a clearly indicated purpose?
 Understanding:
o Is a sound understanding of relevant issues demonstrated?
o Is the exposition of others’ views accurate?
o Are technical terms adequately defined?
 Originality:
o Is there evidence of independent thought?
o Is there critical engagement with the material?
 Argument:
o Is the argument convincing?
o Are the inferences valid?
o Are obvious objections anticipated?
Page 14 of 19
Grade Bands
Fail (less than 40)
Third Class (40–49):





Writing is generally unclear. Frequent spelling or grammar mistakes, incorrect
language, and/or excessively convoluted sentence structure.
Neglects clearly to state a thesis or position and/or fails to support this with
arguments. Contains irrelevant material, or material whose relevance is not
adequately explained.
Demonstrates a barely adequate understanding of central issues. Contains
several errors in exposition or in explanation of concepts.
No evidence of independent thought or critical engagement. Merely rehashes
arguments from readings or lectures.
Where arguments are given, these are weak, depend on invalid inferences or
implausible premises. Fails to anticipate obvious objections.
Lower Second Class (50–59):





Writing is generally clear, but there are occasional spelling/grammar infelicities
and/or poorly constructed sentences.
A thesis/position is indicated but not clearly defined. Some arguments given, but
their structure often unclear.
Demonstrates a basic grasp of key concepts, but occasional inaccuracies in
exposition/explanation.
Little evidence of independent thought. Some suggestion of original ideas, but
these are under-developed and/or expressed unclearly.
Arguments generally weak or unconvincing.
Upper Second Class (60–69):





Writing is generally clear, marred only by the rare spelling/grammar infelicity or
poorly constructed sentence.
A thesis/position is indicated and clearly defined. Arguments are given with
relatively clear structure. It is generally clear what is going on in each section,
why one section follows on from the previous one, and how the essay as a whole
hangs together.
Demonstrates a solid understanding of the key concepts, and the exposition is
generally accurate and thorough.
Substantial evidence of original thought – either an original argument of some
kind for a familiar position or an original argument for a novel position. In either
case, the argument should be reasonably well developed.
The author’s original arguments are interesting and promising, but fairly central
or glaring problems with the argument are not discussed or addressed in any
way, or are given only a highly cursory treatment.
Low First Class (70–79):
Page 15 of 19





Writing is very clear and engaging throughout. Where examples are used they
are both relevant and memorable. The writing will also be concise.
The essay’s structure is not only clear and well defined; it also provides a
satisfying narrative arc.
Demonstrates a deep understanding of the key concepts. Explains other
philosopher’s ideas in the author’s own terms, clearly presenting those ideas in a
way that indicates that the author has “made them his/her own.” Where technical
terms are used they are always carefully defined.
Highly original thought, with well developed arguments. The exegesis will
generally be sufficiently concise as to allow the author to develop his or her own
arguments in considerable detail.
The author very carefully considers the most central and obvious problems with
his/her original argument(s) and has interesting things to say about them.
Mid-First Class (80–89):





Writing is crystal clear and highly engaging throughout. Memorable examples are
used to underscore key points. The writing is concise without coming across as
terse or stilted.
The essay’s structure is clear and well defined, with a highly satisfying narrative
arc.
Demonstrates a deep understanding of key concepts. Not only explains the ideas
of other philosophers in a way that shows he/she has “made them his/her own,”
but that actually casts new light on how we might charitably understand the ideas
of those philosophers.
Very original thought, above and beyond what we would normally expect from an
undergraduate. These original ideas will be developed in great detail.
The author very carefully considers the most central and obvious problems with
his/her original argument(s) and has prima facie convincing rejoinders. Author
may also consider more subtle objections to his/her argument(s)/view(s).
High First Class (90–100):





Writing is extremely clear, concise, and engaging — of a publishable quality.
The essay’s structure is extremely clear and well-defined, with a highly satisfying
narrative arc.
Demonstrates a deep understanding of key concepts. Not only explains the ideas
of other philosophers in a way that shows he/she has “made them his/her own,”
but that actually casts new light on how we might charitably understand the ideas
of those philosophers.
A highly original and well developed line of argument and/or novel view, such
that the essay is publishable, at least in an undergraduate or postgraduate
journal, perhaps bordering on being publishable in a mainstream professional
journal.
The author considers the most important objections to his/her arguments/views.
The replies are generally convincing and subtle. If space allows, less obvious
objections may also be discussed in interesting ways.
Page 16 of 19
11. Making the most of University
Support from your University Careers Service
Your University Careers Service is here to support you from Day 1, not just your
final year. We can assist you in finding semester-time, vacation and volunteering work
to help you finance and add value to your university experience, alongside your studies.
And we are happy to help you explore your future direction, whatever year you’re in.
Whilst studying to gain the best degree you can is your priority, it’s also a good idea to
take advantage of the wide range of opportunities open to you as an undergraduate.
These include, volunteering, mentoring, taking on a role with a student society or club,
study abroad, group projects, part time work, summer jobs, delivering presentations,
work shadowing, to name but a few.
Getting involved with activities outwith your studies has many advantages. You
can:
-
Develop and demonstrate skills and attributes, such as teamwork,
communication, time-management, customer service etc. Future employers will be
looking for evidence of relevant skills from all areas of your life, not just your
studies.
-
Broaden your horizons – new experiences can change your perspective, provide
new insights, alter your outlook, encourage you to consider different opportunities
and directions.
-
Discover your strengths – what you’re good at, what you enjoy, how you can use
these strengths to your advantage in the workplace
Careers Service support includes:
-
Part time and vacation opportunities via our SAGE (Student and Graduate
Employment) database.
-
Support with applications and interviews for part-time and vacation work
-
Volunteering opportunities nationwide and abroad
-
Talking through your immediate and future plans with a Careers Adviser.
- Information specifically for early-years students http://tinyurl.com/lrv7an9
Browse our website www.ed.ac.uk/careers for further information on all the above, or
call in and see us on the 3rd floor of the Main Library Building.
And specifically for Philosophy students:
-
Your own careers blog http://pplscareersblog.wordpress.com/ - regular postings
relevant to PPLS students, to inform and inspire.
-
regular drop-in sessions for quick career queries in DSB/7 George Sq, - look out for
the emails advertising these sessions
-
dedicated Philosophy careers pages www.ppls.ed.ac.uk > philosophy >
undergraduate. Be inspired by:
-
case studies of recent philosophy graduates,
-
the Employability Guide for Philosophy students,
-
your Options with a Philosophy degree …. and more.
We look forward to working with you during your time at Edinburgh.
Page 17 of 19
12. Feedback
You will get many feedback or feedforward opportunities in your courses. Feedback could be in
the form of an essay, a draft write-up, self-generated or peer feedback, small group discussions
or quizzes within lectures etc. Feedforward might include a discussion of how to write an essay,
or prepare for an exam.
Feedback is essential to learning and it takes many forms. We strongly encourage you to use all
forms of feedback, including:










Asking and answering questions in lectures or classes
Asking questions of your Course Organiser or lecturer in their office hours
Discussing your work with lecturers and examiners on Philosophy's dedicated Feedback
Days (Honours students)
Actively participating in your tutorials (pre-Honours students)
Actively participating in Autonomous Learning Groups (Honours students)
Talking about your ideas outside class with fellow Philosophy students
Taking your essay to PhilSoc essay surgeries
Participating in PhilSoc discussion groups and study-skills events
Participating in PhilSoc debates and talks: http://euphilsoc.weebly.com/
Participating in the British Undergraduate Philosophy Society, including undergraduate
conferences: http://www.bups.org
If you have any suggestions on how to improve feedback further, please contact either:





Your Tutor (pre-Honours students)
Your Course Organiser
Your Personal Tutor
Sarah Nicol or Mhari Davidson, the PPLS Student Support Officers
([email protected] or [email protected])
Dr Mark Sprevak, Director of Undergraduate Teaching ([email protected])
Page 18 of 19
13. Students on a Tier 4 visa
As a Tier 4 student, the University of Edinburgh is the sponsor of your UK visa. The
University has a number of legal responsibilities, including monitoring your attendance
on your programme and reporting to the Home Office where:

you suspend your studies, transfer or withdraw from a course, or complete your
studies significantly early;

you fail to register/enrol at the start of your course or at the two additional
registration sessions each year and there is no explanation;

you are repeatedly absent or are absent for an extended period and are excluded
from the programme due to non-attendance. This includes missing Tier 4 census
points without due reason. The University must maintain a record of your attendance
and the Home Office can ask to see this or request information about it at any time;
As a student with a Tier 4 visa sponsored by the University of Edinburgh, the terms of
your visa require you to, (amongst others):

Ensure you have a correct and valid visa for studying at the University of Edinburgh,
which, if a Tier 4 visa, requires that it is a visa sponsored by the University of
Edinburgh;

Attend all of your University classes, lectures, tutorials, etc where required. This
includes participating in the requirements of your course including submitting
assignments, attending meetings with tutors and attending examinations . If you
cannot attend due to illness, for example, you must inform your School. This
includes attending Tier 4 Census sessions when required throughout the academic
session.

Make sure that your contact details, including your address and contact numbers are
up to date in your student record.

Make satisfactory progress on your chosen programme of studies.

Observe the general conditions of a Tier 4 General student visa in the UK, including
studying on the programme for which your visa was issued, not overstaying the
validity of your visa and complying with the work restrictions of the visa.
Please note that any email relating to your Tier 4 sponsorship, including census dates
and times will be sent to your University email address - you should therefore check this
regularly.
Further details on the terms and conditions of your Tier 4 visa can be found in the
“Downloads” section at www.ed.ac.uk/immigration
Information or advice about your Tier 4 immigration status can be obtained by
contacting the International Student Advisory Service, located at the International Office,
33 Buccleuch Place, Edinburgh EH8 9JS
Email: [email protected]
Page 19 of 19